Article Text

We could be heroes: ethical issues with the pre-recruitment of research participants
  1. David Hunter
  1. Professor David Hunter, Southgate Institute, Flinders University, Bedford Park, Adelaide, SA 5050, Australia; david.hunter{at}flinders.edu.au

Abstract

Pre-recruitment is the practice of recruiting potential participants to a list of potential research volunteers in general rather than to a specific research project. This is a relatively common practice in commercial medical research as it reduces the time and hence costs of recruitment and makes it possible to be more efficient by recruiting participants who may be useful for a variety of different pieces of research. It focuses on present practices in the UK although the conclusions and suggestions should be read more widely than this, applying in any situation where pre-recruitment is used as a recruitment tool for clinical trials and beyond. Current pre-recruitment practices in the UK clash significantly with what are seen as best practices and ethical guidance with regard to recruiting participants to individual trials, and insofar as this undermines these practices should be reformed.

  • Clinical trials
  • Informed Consent
  • Policy Guidelines/Inst. Review Boards/Review Cttes.
  • Regulation
  • Research Ethics

Statistics from Altmetric.com

Request Permissions

If you wish to reuse any or all of this article please use the link below which will take you to the Copyright Clearance Center’s RightsLink service. You will be able to get a quick price and instant permission to reuse the content in many different ways.

Introduction

Pre-recruitment is the practice of recruiting participants to a list of potential research volunteers in general rather than to a specific research project. Pre-recruitment is beneficial because it makes the conduct of clinical trials more efficient by facilitating the quick and easy recruitment of participants. As such, it is a useful practice which facilitates the conduct of good quality science. This is a relatively common practice in commercial medical research; however, current practices in the UK and perhaps elsewhere clash significantly with what are seen as best practices and ethical guidance with regard to recruiting participants to individual trials, and insofar as this undermines these practices need to be reformed. While I’ll discuss this in the UK context, similar implications hold wherever pre-recruitment is used.

Internationally, clinical trials are now highly regulated, primarily but not exclusively, via research ethics committees.1 The recruitment of research participants is a central focus of ethics committee review.2 These committees have evolved a set of norms to govern the recruitment of research participants:

  1. Participants should freely choose to be involved, not be induced, but may be compensated for time and the inconvenience of participating. Typically the amount of compensation shouldn't be emphasised.

  2. No coercion is to be used in the recruitment process—for example, the usage of non-emotive language is preferred.

  3. Fully informed consent must be obtained—so, for example, the research participant shouldn't be misled with regard to the likely success of the research.3

These well-established norms have likewise been absorbed by industry, with the Association of the British Pharmaceutical Industry (ABPI) stating in its code of practice for clinical trials that the recruitment of research participants to specific individual trials must be approved by an authorised ethics committee.4 And that conditions of that approval will include advertising in a neutral fashion, ensuring that participants have full and balanced information and that they are not coerced.4

Given this, I was surprised to hear my local radio in Staffordshire advertising thusly: “Be a hero, volunteer for medical research and if you are selected you could earn thousands of pounds” which is clearly contrary to the central norms of recruitment to clinical trials. When I looked at the websites of this company and others engaged in pre-recruitment, similar issues came up.i So, for example, if you look at the website of http://www.trials4us.co.uk, you will see the headline banner is: “We need healthy and patient volunteers for paid clinical trials starting Now” and suggests “As a medical trial volunteer, you are helping to find a cure or simply improve the standard of living for millions of people and sufferers of varying medical conditions worldwide.” It has links to sections on getting paid to participate, and even suggests a referral fee for recruiting friends.ii,5 I'm not picking on http://www.trials4us.co.uk as a lone example; there are several companies recruiting in this fashion. In effect, what these companies are doing is applying traditional marketing techniques to the recruitment of clinical trial volunteers. However, it seems conflicts occur between the appropriate conduct of research and thinking about recruitment of research participants in traditional marketing terms.

These adverts appear to violate the three well-established general requirements of the recruitment of research participants that I outlined above and the industry endorses. They emphasise in emotive language the likely benefits for others of participating, they focus on the financial recompense and portray the research as likely to succeed. So, we would normally deem such recruitment to be unethical, failing to appropriately respect autonomy, and an ethics committee wouldn't allow it. However, pre-recruitment falls into a regulatory loophole, since present regulations apply exclusively to the direct recruitment of participants into specific trials. Since the advert was for general recruitment rather than to a specific trial, there is no formal regulation of this activity. You do not currently need research ethics committee approval to approach people to pre-recruit them, nor is there any formal guidance for this sort of recruitment either from the Health Research Authority (HRA) or from the ABPI.

The present disparity in practices of the pre-recruitment and recruitment of research participants seems problematic—to put it starkly, if you are recruited onto a list of potential participants on the promise of riches and heroism via clinical trials and are then recruited from that list into a specific trial in a much more neutral fashion, your beliefs about the actual trial will be informed by what you were told during pre-recruitment—in other words, you will think you are being heroic and earning lots of money, precisely the views that the current regulations are trying to prevent participants from having. As such, unregulated pre-recruitment runs the risk of making a mockery of the careful standards which have evolved to try and protect people from exploitation and harm in clinical trials. This provides a strong prima facie reason to harmonise our regulations—given that the point of pre-recruitment is to eventually recruit participants to specific trials, we ought to ensure that the norms regarding such specific recruitment are protected by regulating pre-recruitment to the same standard.

Before we rush to regulate pre-recruitment, however, it is worth considering whether there are any significant objections to harmonisation by regulating it. I'll consider two main objections, first that our current standards might be too high and second that these sorts of activities might not be able to be regulated.

1. Our present standards require too much

There is a fairly prominent position in the research ethics literature which argues that research ethics committees ought as a general rule not be particularly bothered about inducement.6–8 The central line of this argument is a critique of the asymmetrical treatment of paid and unpaid participation in research. The supporters of the moral unproblematic nature of inducements argue that if a piece of research is safe enough for people to do it unpaid, then it is at best very odd to deny people the opportunity to do it for pay. Hence, these authors claim, research ethics committees should stop risky research because it is risky not because it involves inducements.

Broadly, this is an argument that tacitly relies on rejecting research exceptionalism (the view we should treat research as morally different or special).1 Similar arguments could be offered against the other two standard practices regarding consent. For example, we could hold coercive language in participant information sheets as permissible since in many other areas such as health promotion, for example, we don’t see emotive language as coercive and objectionable with regard to autonomy and informed consent.

I suspect there are problems with these arguments since I think some forms of research exceptionalism are justified (broadly because researchers are professionals with special duties and an innate conflict of interests).1 But that aside, even if we endorse these arguments against well-established practice in research ethics, there are two further objections to the disparity between the recruitment practices with regard to participants and pre-participants.

First, if our current standards are too high, then this is a ground to change those standards in all cases, not just when people are recruited indirectly. Second, even if our current standards are too high, we might be concerned that effectively flouting them in this case would indirectly undermine researchers respect for regulation in general.9 So, unless we also change the current regulation of recruitment in clinical research to be equally permissive, we should still resist this disparity since it may undermine other norms of research ethics and ethical behaviour.

2. Can pre-recruitment be regulated?

We might be concerned, however, that pre-recruitment may prove to be difficult or even impossible to regulate—if this is the case, then it would be foolish to try and regulate it, since the inevitable failure would itself undermine respect for regulation.

There are many forms of pre-recruitment, including the very common practice of simply keeping files on current participants and recontacting them when you run a future trial. How can all these forms be regulated? I think this objection imagines prospective review as the only arrow in the quiver of research ethics regulation—a common thought since once you have a hammer all problems look like nails. And I think it would be a serious mistake to try and ensure that all pre-recruitment receive external ethical reviews before they are conducted—the sheer volume of pre-recruitment and the costs of review both for researchers and for committee members would make this very challenging.

Still there are other regulatory options that could ensure that pre-recruitment is conducted appropriately. For example, if we agree that the standards for pre-recruitment should be the same as those for specific recruitment, then the HRA, the ABPI and other relevant professional bodies could issue appropriate guidance for pre-recruitment along these lines. Then, when projects reach the stage of seeking ethical approval, the national form could request that the committee be informed if any pre-recruited participants are to be used and the recruitment literature provided. Then, if the ethics committee feels the pre-recruitment didn't met the established standards, it can reject the usage of those pre-recruited participants. This would provide a strong incentive for commercial companies to pre-recruit participants in line with the norms of recruitment onto specific trials.

Conclusions

While there is some controversy about how research recruitment should be regulated, having two different systems of trial participant recruitment with countervailing norms which feed into each other seems inevitably problematic. Hence, regulation should be reformed to capture both systems of recruitment with a transparent defensible set of rules and guidelines. There are a number of ways this reformation could be achieved, from the promulgation of voluntary guidelines from bodies such as the ABPI to hard regulation such as governmental law making to soft regulation through to research ethics committees forbidding the use of pre-recruitment unless it is conducted with regard to the sorts of standards I have outlined in this paper. At a minimum, until something is done at a regulatory level, research ethics committees should request copies of any recruitment literature used in pre-recruitment to assess their suitability.

References

Supplementary materials

  • Supplementary Data

    This web only file has been produced by the BMJ Publishing Group from an electronic file supplied by the author(s) and has not been edited for content.

    Files in this Data Supplement:

Footnotes

Linked Articles

  • The concise argument
    Julian Savulescu

Other content recommended for you