Article Text

Download PDFPDF

Mistakes and missed opportunities regarding cosmetic surgery and conscientious objection
  1. Toni C Saad
  1. Correspondence to Toni C Saad, School of Medicine, Cardiff University, UHW Main Building, Heath Park, Cardiff CF14 4XN, UK; tonisaad1{at}hotmail.com

Abstract

In her paper ‘Cosmetic surgery and conscientious objection’, Minerva rightly identifies cosmetic surgery as an interesting test case for the question of conscientious objection in medicine. Her treatment of this important subject, however, seems problematic. It is argued that Minerva's suggestion that a doctor has a prima facie duty to satisfy patient preferences even against his better clinical judgment, which we call Patient Preference Absolutism, must be regarded with scepticism. This is because (1) it overlooks an important distinction regarding autonomy's meaning and place in clinical practice, and (2) it makes obsolete the important concepts of expert clinical judgment and beneficence. Finally, we discuss two ideas which emerge from consideration of cosmetic surgery in relation to conscientious objection. These are the possible analogy between clinical judgment and conscientious objection, and the possible role the goals of medicine can play in defining the scope of conscientious objection.

  • Conscientious Objection
  • Autonomy
  • Capacity

Statistics from Altmetric.com

Request Permissions

If you wish to reuse any or all of this article please use the link below which will take you to the Copyright Clearance Center’s RightsLink service. You will be able to get a quick price and instant permission to reuse the content in many different ways.

Introduction

In her paper ‘Cosmetic surgery and conscientious objection’,1 Minerva rightly identifies cosmetic surgery as an interesting test case for the question of conscientious objection (CO) in medicine. Her treatment of this important subject, however, seems to miss the crucial significance of cosmetic surgery in contrast to medicine in general: their differing relationship to the goals of medicine. My response discusses two major problems that emerge from Minerva's analysis. These are (1) what I have called her principle of Patient Preference Absolutism, and (2) the redundancy of beneficence and clinical judgment which results from it. Finally, I briefly outline the significance cosmetic surgery bears in relation to CO.

Patient Preference Absolutism

I venture that most clinicians would find Minerva's suggestion quite astonishing that it is ‘plausible that some patients may request interventions aimed at changing their features in a way that the surgeon might consider against a patient's best interest’, but that this does not necessarily ‘provide them [the surgeon] with a good reason to refuse to perform it’.1 ,i The idea that a surgeon must do something which he judges not to be in a patient's best interest simply because the patient requests or prefers it I call Patient Preference Absolutism (the reciprocal concept to Conscience Absolutismii, which Minerva criticises explicitly in another paper2). There are good reasons to doubt it. First, it overlooks an important distinction regarding patient autonomy; second, it risks severely undermining the concept of beneficence and the place of clinical expert judgment in medical practice.

Autonomy and preference

A young woman presents to emergency department with severe abdominal pain. The surgeons diagnose appendicitis and recommend immediate surgical intervention, knowing the possibly fatal consequences of doing otherwise. The young woman (who has capacity) refuses surgery, and requests alternative treatment. The surgeons reluctantly begin a course of intravenous antibiotics, though surgery, in their professional opinion, is in her best interests; conservative management is not—though it is better than nothing.iii The surgeons still have a duty of care towards her, and must therefore do what is second best. Unwise though her decision might be, she has the autonomy to refuse surgery. And if autonomy means anything, it means the right to say no.3 This negative autonomy is important, and should be respected. As Paul Ramsay famously said, “no man is good enough to cure another without his consent.”4 There is little question that, at least under normal circumstances, this sort of autonomy exists, and doctors must allow it to be exercised.

But, if an elderly man complaining of occasional episodes of gout in his foot requests referral for the amputation of his toe—which is clearly not in his best interests—his doctor is not obliged to comply. And even if he did, a surgeon would have no duty to perform the operation if he judged it not to be in the patient's best interest (or against his best interests).iv Just as patients have a right to say no, so do doctors. Patients do not have absolute positive autonomy concerning their treatment, and doctors must respect the patient's right to say no. In normal circumstances, a doctor cannot rightly force a patient to do what he believes is in his best interests, but neither can a patient force a doctor to do comply with his preferences.v 5 Therefore, a doctor may only act against a patient's best interests negatively, that is, by omission of refused treatment. He has no duty to positively do (without further qualification) what a patient requests, even if their decision harms only themselves. Most practitioners would consider this to be stating the obvious. Patient Preference Absolutism, whereby a patient has absolute positive autonomy, is practically unimaginable.

Moreover, if a doctor meets a patient's request for something which he believes to be positively harmful, he calls into question his character. Did he not have the courage of his professional conviction to withhold treatment? Integrity, important to medical practice,6 becomes impossible (or irrelevant) if there exists a prima facie duty to satisfy patient preferences. Furthermore, Patient Request Absolutism undermines another basic element of human interaction: beneficence.

What about beneficence?

Considerations of beneficence seem to collapse into Minerva's understanding of autonomy as requiring a duty to maximise preference satisfaction: ‘surgeons do not have a good reason to refuse to perform the treatment if competent and autonomous patients think that undergoing such interventions is worthwhile and is in their best interests because it satisfies their preferences and increases their level of well-being’.1 The unexplained assumption here is that the fact of preference satisfaction is to be equated with well-being.vi This is perhaps the premise from which the argument for Patient Preference Absolutism stems, but it too is unsubstantiated.

Regardless, this focus on preference satisfaction obviates perhaps the most basic principle of ethics: beneficence. The concept is without content if preference satisfaction is the rule of conduct, or if it is entirely reducible to respect for positive preference. Most doctors take it for granted that there is more to their duty to do good than merely doing as the patient says.vii Additionally, leading theories of medical ethics distinguish between, and carefully balance, beneficence and autonomy.7 So, if beneficence is reducible to acquiescence, it is hard to see how it can have any continuing significance in ethics.

Those who make the daily difficult clinical decisions at the bedside would be in little doubt that it is not beneficent to operate if non-invasive treatments suffice, nor to amputate if a course of antibiotics is curative, nor to give futile or unnecessarily burdensome treatment—even if these satisfy patient preferences. Equating human well-being with untrammelled fulfilment of preferences is far removed from the reality of making well the sick. It makes beneficence obsolete by collapsing it into preference utilitarianism, and renders redundant professional judgment. It would not be controversial among medical professionals to say that this would be a most undesirable result.

A missed opportunity

The subject of cosmetic surgery in relation to CO provides an opportunity to explore the distinction between professional and moral judgment. Unfortunately, Minerva's assumption that a request has prima facie priority simply because it expresses preference obscures this, as well as the common-sense distinction between the respective goals of cosmetic surgery and medicine more generally. This is a double missed opportunity.

First, because, as suggested above, there is a significant difference between refusal on moral grounds and refusal on grounds of clinical judgment. The clinical judgment of an expert is not the same sort of thing as his moral concerns. Not satisfying patient preferences often has more to do with clinical judgment than ‘moral permissibility’.1 Not all objection is strictly moral. Patient Preference Absolutism cannot account for this; it does not engage with the matter. The belief that moral/CO cannot be admitted does not necessarily entail anything about clinical objection. It is regrettable that this important distinction remains unexplored by Minerva, for it has been mostly ignored in the literature so far.viii It would be interesting to consider the possible analogy between clinical judgment and ‘moral’ judgments in clinical medicine.

Second, there is a distinction between medicine in general and cosmetic surgery which has not yet informed the CO debate. Their goals are very different: the restoration and maintenance of health for the former and the enhancement of appearance for the latter.ix Hence, one can argue that there is something specific to what a doctor qua doctor must do, which is not necessarily identical to what a cosmetic surgeon does (though the craft of the latter presupposes similar expertise to the former). The things which a doctor does qua doctor are not necessarily to be directly equated with what a doctor does, for doctors can apply their craft to evil ends as well as good ones.x If a procedure does not conform to the goals of medicine, then it is unclear that it is a medical practitioner's duty to do it. Even if female genital mutilation were a routine procedure (as some envisage9), it would not be a doctor's duty to perform it, for the intentional mutilation of genitals does not conform to the goals of medicine. Whether his refusal is moral or not is largely irrelevant, since he is merely refusing to do something which he has no professional duty to do. The same reasoning might apply to ritual circumcision, body enhancements and active euthanasia. It is regrettable that current literature on CO largely overlooks its relation to the goals of medicine. Minerva's paper is another missed opportunity in this regard.

Conclusion

Cosmetic surgery is a useful test case for the debate around CO, though Minerva's treatment of it obscures key distinctions which could advance the current debate. Additionally, the principle of Patient Preference Absolutism threatens two things at the heart of good medical practice: clinical judgment and beneficence. Minerva's vision of medical practice without these is as unappealing as it is impractical to medical practitioners, and therefore merits strong scepticism.

References

Footnotes

  • Competing interests None declared.

  • Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; internally peer reviewed.

  • i Criticising this assertion is difficult, however, not least because Minerva does not appear to distinguish between cosmetic surgery and medicine in general (this will be in considered more later).

  • ii Conscience Absolutism is the theoretical principle which permits a doctor to conscientiously object to anything to which he has a moral aversion, without further qualification, and without compromise.

  • iii In a sense, it comes to be in her best interests after the possibility of surgery is excluded.

  • iv It will not do to argue that merely believing that an amputation is in his best interests indicated loss of capacity because it shows that he cannot weigh up the information being presented to him. In general, eccentricity, caprice and stubbornness are not necessarily a sign of mental incapacity.

  • v Of course, when there are genuine, rational clinical choices to be made, it is quite appropriate for a patient to choose from among them.

  • vi For example, ‘people who chose to undergo surgery for reasons I have labelled as whimsical, have also benefited from being enabled to follow their whimsical desire’.1

  • vii The same could probably be said of almost every reasonable human being.

  • viii Mark Wicclair, perhaps the most prolific writer on the subject of CO, appears to omit its consideration completely from his discussion.8

  • ix This distinction explains why cosmetic surgery is rarely funded in the public sector. It is generally not taken to be as important as medicine in general, which aims at the restoration of health—to put it in simplistic terms. There is much debate to be had about the goals of medicine.

  • x For example, the horrors done to Chinese prisoners at Unit 731 by Japanese doctors. Though these perpetrators were doctors, and drew on their medical training, in doing so they were not acting as doctors qua doctors.