Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-xxrs7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T06:07:17.667Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Normative Justification for Distinguishing the Ethics of Clinical Research from the Ethics of Medical Care

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

In the research ethics literature, there is strong disagreement about the ethical acceptability of placebo-controlled trials, particularly when a tested therapy aims to alleviate a condition for which standard treatment exists. Recently, this disagreement has given rise to debate over the moral appropriateness of the principle of clinical equipoise for medical research. Underlying these debates are two fundamentally different visions of the moral obligations that investigators owe their subjects.

Some commentators and ethics documents claim that physicians, whether acting as care givers or researchers, have the same duty of beneficence towards their patients and subjects: namely, that they must provide optimal medical care. In discussing placebo surgery in research on refractory Parkinson's disease, Peter Clark succinctly states this view: “The researcher has an ethical responsibility to act in the best interest of subjects.”

Type
Independent
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

See e.g., Sugarman, J., “Using Empirical Data to Inform the Ethical Evaluation of Placebo Controlled Trials,” Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (2004): 2935; Miller, F. G. Brody, H., “What Makes Placebo-Controlled Trials Unethical?” American Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 2 (2002): 3–9; Veatch, R. M., “Subject Indifference and the Justification of Placebo-Controlled Trials,” American Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 2 (2002): 12–13; Lemmens, T. Miller, P. B., “Avoiding a Jekyll-And-Hyde Approach to the Ethics of Clinical Research and Practice,” American Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 2 (2002): 14–17; Emanuel, E. J. Miller, F. G., “The Ethics of Placebo-Controlled Trials – A Middle Ground,” N. Engl. J. Med. 345 (2001): 915–19; Freedman, B. Glass, K. C. Weijer, C., “Placebo Orthodoxy in Clinical Research II: Ethical, Legal, and Regulatory Myths,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 24 (1996): 252–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See e.g., Miller, F. G. Brody, H., “A Critique of Clinical Equipoise: Therapeutic Misconception in the Ethics of Clinical Trials,” Hastings Center Report 33, no. 3 (2003): 1928; Weijer, C. Miller, P. B., “Therapeutic Obligation in Clinical Research,” Hastings Center Report 33, no. 3 (2003): 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, P., “Placebo Surgery For Parkinson's Disease: Do the Benefits Outweigh the Risks?” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 30 (2002): 5868, at 62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Medical Association, “Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects,” adopted in 1964 and amended in 1975, 1983, 1989, 1996, and 2000, reprinted in JAMA 284 (2000): 3043–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemmens, T. Miller, P.B., supra note 1.Google Scholar
Id. at 14, 15. David Steinberg similarly questions the ethical relevance of the divergent goals of research and care: “The dominant goals of clinical research and clinical care may differ; however, the existence of a goal does not suffice as its moral justification.” Steinberg, D., “Clinical Research should not be Permitted to Escape the Ethical Orbit of Clinical Care,” American Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 2 (2002): 2728, at 27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, P. B. Weijer, C., “Rehabilitating Equipoise,” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13 (2003): 93118, at 110–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M., What We Owe To Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Id. at 106.Google Scholar
Kumar, R., “Reasonable Reasons in Contractualist Moral Argument,” Ethics 114, no. 1 (2003): 637, at 14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id. at 14.Google Scholar
Id. at 14; Scanlon, supra note 8, at 204, 251.Google Scholar
Emanuel, E. J. et al., “Scandals and Tragedies of Research with Human Participants (Introduction to Part I),” in Emanuel, E. J. et al., eds., Ethical and Regulatory Aspects of Clinical Research (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2003): 15, at 1.Google Scholar
Emanuel, E. J. et al., “Preface,” in Emanuel, E. J. et al., eds., Ethical and Regulatory Aspects of Clinical Research (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2003): xvxviii, at xv.Google Scholar
For a discussion of the different legal duties that should guide clinical research and practice, respectively, based on the different ethical duties supported by the distinctive goals of those enterprises, see Morreim, E. H., “Litigation in Clinical Research: Malpractice Doctrines Versus Research Realities,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 32 (2004): 474484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emanuel, E. J. Wendler, D. Grady, C., “What Makes Clinical Research Ethical?” JAMA 283 (2000): 27012711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id. at 2701–2702. These documents include the Nuremberg Code, the Declaration of Helsinki, the Belmont Report, International Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects, as well as others.Google Scholar
Id. at 2701, citing Levine, R. J., Ethics and Regulation in Clinical Research, 2nd ed. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1988).Google ScholarPubMed
Miller, F. G. Brody, H., supra note 1.Google Scholar
Emanuel, E. J. Wendler, D. Grady, C., supra note 17, at 2708.Google Scholar
Glass, K. C., Letter to the Editor, “Clinical Equipoise and the Therapeutic Misconception,” Hastings Center Report 33, no. 5 (2003): 56, at 5.Google Scholar
Freedman, B. Glass, K. C. Weijer, C., supra note 2, at 253.Google Scholar
Steinberg, , supra note 6, at 27.Google Scholar
Scanlon, , supra note 8, at 248–56.Google Scholar
Id. at 252.Google Scholar
Id. at 253.Google Scholar
Appelbaum, P. S. Grisso, T. Frank, E. et al., “Competence of Depressed Patients for Consent to Research,” American Journal of Psychiatry 156 (1999): 1380–84.Google Scholar
Emanuel, E. J. Miller, F. G., supra note 2; Freedman, B. Glass, K. C. Weijer, C., supra note 2.Google Scholar
Appelbaum, P. S. Lidz, C. W. Grisso, T., “Therapeutic Misconception in Clinical Research: Frequency and Risk Factors,” IRB 26, no. 2 (2004): 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, F. G. Rosenstein, D. L., “The Therapeutic Orientation to Clinical Trials,” N. Engl. J. Med. 348 (2003): 1383–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Medical Association, supra note 4.Google Scholar
Appelbaum, P. S., “A Theory of Ethics for Forensic Psychiatry,” The Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 25 (1997): 233247, at 239.Google Scholar