Skip to main content
Log in

Explaining the Identifiable Victim Effect

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is widely believed that people are willing to expend greater resources to save the lives of identified victims than to save equal numbers of unidentified or statistical victims. There are many possible causes of this disparity which have not been enumerated previously or tested empirically. We discuss four possible causes of the identifiable victim effect and present the results of two studies which indicate that the most important cause of the disparity in treatment of identifiable and statistical lives is that, for identifiable victims, a high proportion of those at risk can be saved.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Batson, C. Daniel, et al. (1991). “Empathic joy and the empathy-altruism hypothesis.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 62, 413–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bullard, Robert D. (1993). Confronting Environmental Racism: Voices from the Grassroots. Boston: South End Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calabresi, Guido, and Philip Bobbitt (1978). Tragic Choices. New York: W.W. Norton and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cialdini, Robert B., et al. (1987). “Empathy-based helping: is it selflessly or selfishly motivated?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52, 749–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M, J. Y. Jaffray, and T. Said (1987). “Experimental comparison of individual behavior under risk and under uncertainty for gains and for losses,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 39, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, John H. Jr. (1994). “Clinton to Order Effort to Make Pollution Fairer,” The NewYork Times, February 10, page A1.

  • Douglas, Mary (1992). Risk and Blame: Essays in Cultural Theory. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, Timothy (1994). “A 3-Strike Law Shows It's Not as Simple as it Seems,” The New York Times, February 15, p. A1.

  • Gibbard, Allan (1986). “Risk and Value,” in Douglas MacLean (Ed.), Values at Risk. New Jersey: Rowan and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillette, Clayton P., and Thomas D. Hopkins (1988). Federal Agency Valuations of Human Life. Administrative Conference of the United States, Report for Recommendation 88–7.

  • Glover, Jonathan (1977). Causing Death and Saving Lives. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Walter (1993). “TV, by its very nature, can stack the deck,” The New York Times, September 13, p. C20.

  • Gore, Al (1992). Earth in the Balance: Ecology and the Human Spirit. New York: Plume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, John K. and Richard T. Carson (1993). “Baseline risk and Preference for Reductions in Risk to Life.” Risk Analysis 13 (2), 457–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeney, Ralph L. (1995). “Understanding Life-Threatening Risks,” Risk Analysis 15 (6).

  • Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk.” Econometrica 47(2).

  • Latané, Bibb, and John M. Darley (1970). The Unresponsive Bystander: Why doesn't he help?. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linden, Eugene (1988). “Helping Out Putu, Siku and Kanik,” Time Magazine, pp. 76–77. October 31.

  • MacLean, Douglas (1986). “Social Values and the Distribution of Risk,” in Douglas MacLean (Ed.), Values at Risk. New Jersey: Rowan and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council (1989). Improving Risk Communication. Washington DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, Richard and Lee Ross (1980). Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • People Weekly (1987). “America's heart goes out to Baby Jessica.” Volume 28:18. November 2.

  • People Weekly (1990). Volume 33:15. April 16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piliavin, Jane A., et al. (1981). Emergency Intervention. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piliavin, Irving M., Judith Rodin, and Jane A. Piliavin (1969). “Good samaritanism: an underground phenomenon?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 13, 289–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Massachussetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raynor, Steve (1992). “Cultural Theory and Risk Analysis,” In Seldon Krimsky and Dominic Golding (Eds.), Social Theories of Risk. Connecticut: Praeger Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redelmeier, Donald A. and Amos Tversky (1990). “Occasional Note: Discrepancy Between Medical Decisions for Individual Patients and for Groups,” The New England Journal of Medicine, April 19.

  • Ritov, Ilana, and Jonathan Baron (1990). “Reluctance to Vaccinate: Omission Bias and Ambiguity,” Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 3, 263–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1968). “The Life You Save May Be Your Own,” in Samuel Chase (Ed.), Problems in Public Expenditure Analysis. Washington DC: The Brookings Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shotland, R. Lance (1983). “What's wrong with helping behavior research? Only the independent and dependent variables.” Academic Psychology Bulletin 5, 339–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. S. (1991). Risk and Rationality: Philosophical Foundations for Populist Reforms. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skelton, George (1993). “A Father's Crusade Born From Pain,” The Los Angeles Times, December 9, p. A3.

  • Slovic, P., B. Fischhoff, and S. Lichtenstein. (1980). “Facts and Fears: Understanding Perceived Risk,” In Richard C. Schwing and Walther A. Albers, Jr. (Eds.), Societal Risk Assessment: How Safe is Safe Enough? New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, S. E. and S. C. Thompson (1982). “Stalking the elusive ‘vividness’ effect.” Psychological Review 89, 155–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toufexis, Anastasia (1993). “The Ultimate Choice.” Time Magazine, pp. 43–44. August 31.

  • Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman (1981). “The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice,” Science 211, 243–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman (1986). “Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions,” Journal of Business 59 (4), part 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Variety (1989). “TV Reviews—Network: Everybody's Baby,” Volume 335:7, May 31.

  • Viscusi, W. Kip and William N. Evans (1990). “Utility Functions That Depend on Health Status: Estimates and Economic Implications,” The American Economic Review 80 (3), 353–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. Kip (1992). Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstein, Milton C., Donald S. Shepard, and Joseph S. Pliskin (1980). “The Economic Value of Changing Mortality Probabilities: A Decision-Theoretic Approach,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 94, 373–396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whipple, Chris (1992). “Inconsistent Values in Risk Management” in Seldon Krimsky and Dominic Golding (Eds.), Social Theories of Risk. Connecticut: Praeger Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

JENNI, K., LOEWENSTEIN, G. Explaining the Identifiable Victim Effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 14, 235–257 (1997). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1007740225484

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1007740225484

Navigation