Defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2009.06.005Get rights and content

Abstract

How should we define ‘health’ and ‘disease’? There are three main positions in the literature. Naturalists desire value-free definitions based on scientific theories. Normativists believe that our uses of ‘health’ and ‘disease’ reflect value judgments. Hybrid theorists offer definitions containing both normativist and naturalist elements. This paper discusses the problems with these views and offers an alternative approach to the debate over ‘health’ and ‘disease’. Instead of trying to find the correct definitions of ‘health’ and ‘disease’ we should explicitly talk about the considerations that are central in medical discussions, namely state descriptions (descriptions of physiological or psychological states) and normative claims (claims about what states we value or disvalue). This distinction avoids the problems facing the major approaches to defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’, and it more clearly captures what matters in medical discussions.

Introduction

How should we define the terms ‘health’ and ‘disease’? This is a central problem in the philosophy of medicine and an important issue in bioethics. There are three main philosophical approaches to defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’. Naturalists (Kendell, 1975, Boorse, 1976, Boorse, 1977, Boorse, 1997, Scadding, 1990) desire definitions based on scientific theory. Their definitions attempt to highlight what is biologically natural and normal for humans. Normativists (Margolis, 1976, Goosens, 1980, Sedgewick, 1982, Engelhardt, 1986) believe that our uses of ‘health’ and ‘disease’ reflect value judgments. Healthy states are those states we desire, and diseased states are those states we want to avoid. Hybrid theorists (Reznek, 1987, Caplan, 1992, Wakefield, 1992) define ‘health’ and ‘disease’ by combining aspects of naturalism and normativism. Their aim is to provide an account of health and disease that captures the virtues but not the vices of naturalism and normativism.

As we shall see, all three approaches to defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’ are problematic. Naturalism does not satisfy its own desideratum of providing naturalistic definitions of ‘health’ and ‘disease’. Normativism attempts but fails to capture how the terms ‘health’ and ‘disease’ are used by lay people and medical practitioners. The hybrid approach, like naturalism, incorrectly assumes that we can give a scientific account of the natural states of organisms. There is also a more systematic problem underlying the debate over defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’. When discussing controversial medical cases, two factors are salient: the physiological or psychological states of patients, and the values we attach to those states. Naturalists focus on physiological and psychological states—whether an organ or system is normal or properly functioning. Normativists focus on whether a psychological or physiological state is valued or disvalued. The debate is regrettably polarized: naturalism and normativism each focus on only one of the two factors that are important when discussing medical cases. Hybrid theorists do consider both components, but they do so in an overly restrictive way. For the hybrid theorist, disease only occurs when a state is both dysfunctional and disvalued. As a result, the hybrid approach to ‘health’ and ‘disease’ too quickly shuts down the discussion of controversial cases.

We could keep looking for the correct definitions of ‘health’ and ‘disease’, but this paper advocates a different approach. Instead of trying to find the correct definitions of ‘health’ and ‘disease’ we should explicitly talk about the considerations that are central in medical discussions, namely state descriptions (descriptions of physiological or psychological states) and normative claims (claims about what states we value or disvalue). Using this distinction avoids the problems facing the major approaches to defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’. Furthermore, this distinction more clearly captures what matters in medical discussions.

Section snippets

Naturalism

Naturalism is the most prominent philosophical approach to defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’ (Boorse, 1976, Boorse, 1977, Boorse, 1997, Kendell, 1975, Scadding, 1990, Wachbroit, 1994a, Wachbroit, 1994b) and Boorse’s definitions are the most influential and well developed naturalist definitions. Many have criticized Boorse’s approach (for example, Reznek, 1987, Wakefield, 1992, Amundson, 2000, Cooper, 2002). We will turn to some of those criticisms shortly. First let us look at Boorse’s most

Normativism

Given the problems with naturalism, should we adopt a normativist approach to ‘health’ and ‘disease’? Normativism has a number of supporters (Margolis, 1976, Goosens, 1980, Sedgewick, 1982, Engelhardt, 1986). Here are two representative quotes:

All sickness is essentially deviancy [from] some alternative state of affairs which is considered more desirable  The attribution of illness always proceeds from the computation of a gap between presented behavior (or feeling) and some social norm. (

Hybrid theories

Let us turn to the hybrid approach to defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’. The hybrid approach attempts to overcome the problems of normativism and naturalism by using both normativist and naturalist elements in its definitions. The hybrid approach has been suggested by several authors (Reznek, 1987, Wakefield, 1992, Caplan, 1992). Wakefield’s account is the most prominent version of that approach. According to Wakefield (he uses the term ‘disorder’ for disease):

A condition is a disorder if and

An alternative approach

We have spent considerable time discussing the three main approaches to defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’. All three approaches are problematic. Naturalism, the most widely accepted approach in philosophy and medicine, fails to satisfy its desideratum of being naturalistic. Normativism fails to achieve its desideratum of accurately describing how we use the terms ‘health’ and ‘disease’. The hybrid approach too quickly shuts down the discussion of controversial cases, and its naturalistic

Concluding remarks

Most philosophers, medical practitioners and lay people think that health and disease are real categories in nature. They believe, in more philosophical terminology, that ‘health’ and ‘disease’ are natural kind terms. Natural kind theorists typically assume that natural kind terms should reflect divisions in nature as specified by our best scientific theories. This is just the tactic naturalists and hybrid theorists adopt. In an effort to define ‘health’ and ‘disease’ they turn to biological

Acknowledgements

My thanks to Ron Amundson, Travis Dumsday, Walter Glannon, Tim Lewens, Dominic Murphy, and a referee of this journal for their helpful suggestions on earlier versions of this paper. I also thank audiences at Washington University in St. Louis, the University of Exeter, Claremont College, and the University of Calgary for their helpful questions. Financial assistance was provided by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, and the Calgary Institute for the Humanities.

References (34)

  • R. Amundson

    Against normal function

    Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

    (2000)
  • R. Cooper

    Disease

    Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

    (2002)
  • Amundson, R. (2005). Disability, ideology, and quality of life: Bias in biomedical ethics. In D. Wasserman, J....
  • Bergman, R., Afifi, A., & Miyauchi, R. (1992–1998). Illustrated encyclopedia of human anatomic variation. Iowa City,...
  • C. Boorse

    What a theory of mental health should be

    Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior

    (1976)
  • C. Boorse

    Health as a theoretical concept

    Philosophy of Science

    (1977)
  • Boorse, C. (1997). A rebuttal on health. In J. Humber, & R. Almeder (Eds.), What is disease? (pp. 1–134). Totowa, NJ:...
  • A. Buchanan et al.

    From chance to choice: Genetics and justice

    (2000)
  • Caplan, A. (1992). If gene theory is the cure, what is the disease? In G. Annas, & S. Elias (Eds.), Gene mapping: Using...
  • T. Engelhardt

    Ideology and etiology

    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy

    (1976)
  • T. Engelhardt

    The foundations of bioethics

    (1986)
  • M. Ereshefsky

    The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy

    (2001)
  • W. Goosens

    Values, health, and medicine

    Philosophy of Science

    (1980)
  • G. Hesslow

    Do we need a concept of disease?

    Theoretical Medicine

    (1993)
  • D. Hull

    A matter of individuality

    Philosophy of Science

    (1978)
  • Cited by (159)

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text