the concept of brain death (BD) refers to two different but strictly
related conditions: the death of the brain ("the irreversible cessation of
all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem"[1]) and the
patient's death certified by neurological criteria.
In his letter, C. Levyman strongly supports both aspects of the
concept. Actually, even if nobody challenges the fact the BD i...
the concept of brain death (BD) refers to two different but strictly
related conditions: the death of the brain ("the irreversible cessation of
all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem"[1]) and the
patient's death certified by neurological criteria.
In his letter, C. Levyman strongly supports both aspects of the
concept. Actually, even if nobody challenges the fact the BD is a point of
no return, many authors have questioned that BD identifies the loss of all
intracranial functions [2-10] and also the equivalence between BD and the
patients biological death has been called into question [6,8,10-17]. The
debate is very fascinating and intriguing. We believe that labeling either
position as regressive/progressive does not help in the discussion, which
should be open and respectful.
On the other hand, this problem is totally unrelated to our paper,
which dealt with the problem of defining the vital status of non-heart-
beating organ donors (NHBD). We argued that, given current protocols
(which are clearly different from the protocols for brain-dead patients),
at the time of organ retrieval it is impossible to define the death of
NHBD on either neurological [18] or cardio/respiratory criteria.
References
(1) The Uniform Determination of Death Act (UDDA), as expressed by the
President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and
Biomedical and Behavioural Research (1981) Defining death: a report on the
medical, legal, and ethical issues in the determination of death.
Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office.
(2) Evans DW, Hill DJ (1989) The brainstem of organ donors are not dead.
Catholic Medical Quarterly. 40: 113-121.
(3) Truog RD, Fackler JC (1992) Rethinking brain death. Crit Care Med
20:1705-1713.
(4) Veatch RM (1993) The impending collapse of the whole-brain death
definition of death. Hasting Center Report 23(4):18-24.
(5) Halevy A, Brody B (1993) Brain death: reconciling definitions, criteria
and tests. Ann Intern Med 119: 519-525.
(6) Singer P (1994) How death was redefined. In: Singer P Rethinking life
and death. The collapse of our traditional ethics. St. Martin's Press, New
York, pp 20-37.
(7) Truog RD (1997) Is it time to abandon brain death? Hasting Center
Report 21:29-37
(8) Kerridge IH, Saul P, Lowe M, McPhee J, Williams D (2002) Death, dying
and donation: organ transplantation and the diagnosis of death. J Med
Ethics 28: 89-94.
(9) Facco E, Munari M, Gallo F, Volpin SM, Behr AU, Baratto F, Giron GP
(2002) Role of short latency evoked potentials in the diagnosis of brain
death. Clinical Neurophysiology 113: 1855-1866.
(10) Truog RD, Robinson MR (2003) Role of brain death and the dead-donor
rule in the ethics of organ transplantation. Crit Care Med, 31(9):2391-
2396.
(11) Danish Council of Ethics (1988). Death Criteria: a report. The Danish
Council of Ethics, Denmark.
(12) Arnold RM, Youngner SJ (1993) The dead donor rule: should we stretch
it, bend it or abandon it? Kennedy Inst Ethics J 3: 263-278
(13) Shewmon DA (1997) Recovery from "brain death": A neurologist's
Apologia. Linacre Quarterly 64:30-96.
(14) Shewmon DA (1998) Chronic “brain death”: meta-analysis and conceptual
consequences. Neurology 51:1538-45.
(15) Shewmon DA (1998) "Brain-stem death", "brain death" and death: a
critical re-evaluation of the purported evidence. Issues Law Med 14: 125-
45.
(16) Shewmon DA (1999) Spinal shock and 'brain death': somatic
pathophysiological equivalence and implications for the integrative-unity
rationale. Spinal Cord 37:313-24.
(17) Shewmon DA (2001) The brain and somatic integration: insights into the
standard biological rationale for equating "brain death" with death. J Med
Philos. 26(5): 457-78.
(18) The Ethics Committee, American College of Critical Care Medicine,
Society of Critical Care Medicine (2001) Recommendations for non-heart-
beating organ donation. A position paper. Crit Care Med 29(9): 1826-1831.
The comments of Marang and Kievit are interesting, but are they relevant?[1]
I fear not, or at best only in part. The authors have failed to answer the question, which I raised and its implication. Therefore I will try to do this myself.
1. Are medical doctors required to present medical information to a judge, if there is a likelihood that the information or evidence can be used in cour...
The comments of Marang and Kievit are interesting, but are they relevant?[1]
I fear not, or at best only in part. The authors have failed to answer the question, which I raised and its implication. Therefore I will try to do this myself.
1. Are medical doctors required to present medical information to a judge, if there is a likelihood that the information or evidence can be used in court against the defendant? The answer is no, since no one needs to provide evidence against him or herself.
2. Where can a judge then find the information he needs, if the defendant remains silent? The answer seems obvious. Both the patient and possibly the patient-organization may have collected data on the average complication frequency in the whole country or/and the specific hospital, where the defendant works. Let me give an example. A number of years ago the Dutch consumer organization, Consumentenbond, reported that some of its members, who were also patients, complained about the high incidence of complications occurring in the department of gynecology in a hospital in the Dutch town of Amersfoort. The medical director of the hospital threatened that he would sue the Consumentenbond if they would not withdraw their complaint. The Consumentenbond, however, did not retract its accusation and an Inspector of Health confirmed the negligence in the department of gynecology. This led to the resignation of the medical director and some of the gynecologists.
3. Are patients able to determine if a complication has occurred and if so if it is caused by an error or if it has occurred spontaneously? In my opinion this will always remain a difficult matter. But undoubtedly with further experience, the quality of the data, collected by the patient-organization, will improve. Here it should be emphasized, that even for the medically trained staff, it may be difficult to detect a complication and to establish its cause. Finally in malpractice cases the degree in which a complication is the result of an error is, I believe, best left to the judge to decide. He will, in general hear the evidence from specialists representing the plaintiff or the defendant. Occasionally the judge, himself selects a medical expert to help him to establish the cause of the complication.
Reference
(1) Marang PJ, Kievit J. Re: Patient organisations should also establish databanks on medical complications [electronic response to Gebhardt DOH; Patient organisations should also establish databanks on medical complications] jmedethics.com 2003http://jme.bmjjournals.com/cgi/eletters/29/2/115#49
In the Journal of Medical Ethics, Joffe et al. recently published an article titled: What do patients value in their hospital care? An empirical perspective on autonomy
centred bioethic [1] This empirical study evaluates whether patients’ willingness to recommend their hospital to others is more strongly associated with their belief that they were treated with...
In the Journal of Medical Ethics, Joffe et al. recently published an article titled: What do patients value in their hospital care? An empirical perspective on autonomy
centred bioethic [1] This empirical study evaluates whether patients’ willingness to recommend their hospital to others is more strongly associated with their belief that they were treated with respect and dignity than with their belief that they had adequate say in their treatment.[see note 1]
Joffe et al. go on to suggest that confirmation of these empirical hypotheses would constitute a prescription for elevating the principle of respect for persons to the level that the principle of respect for autonomy currently enjoys in our model of the ideal patient-physician relationship ([1] p.104). In other words, they suggest that by some means empirical findings could influence our ranking of the normative principles. Earlier in the article, they make an even stronger claim about the influence of empirical data on our acceptance of normative principles. They suggest that if it were demonstrated empirically that some patients prefer to delegate medical decisions to health care professionals a serious challenge would be levied against the normative assumptions underlying the principle of respect for autonomy, at least under the mandatory autonomy view, which holds patients not only have a right but also an obligation to act autonomously ([1] p.103). In light of many recent empirical studies challenging the centrality of patient autonomy and shared decision-making in bioethical theory, I think it is instructive to evaluate the means by which empirical findings, like those offered in Joffe et al., strengthen or weaken our arguments for ethical principles. In particular, I will be interested in how Joffe et al. propose their data lead them to the normative conclusions they reach.
In the last paragraph of their essay, Joffe et al. write, “we do not recommend that patients’ perspectives should unilaterally determine ethical frameworks. We do, however, believe that data such as those presented here can contribute to the search for reflective equilibrium in bioethics”([1] p.107). The term “reflective equilibrium,” as the authors note, was introduced by John Rawls. At least in its first instance, it refers to a way of constructing a moral theory by balancing one’s considered moral judgments against one’s moral principles, until one’s judgments and principles form a consistent set—that is, a moral theory (Rawls [2], p.288). Joffe et al.’s idea seems to be that by surveying patients’ perspectives they will be able to capture one side of this equilibrium, considered moral judgments or moral principles (they do not specify which), and in so doing contribute to the desired end: a consistent ethical framework to govern medical encounters, built (at least in part) from the principles and moral judgments of the patient community. Whatever the merits of this goal, however, Joffe et al. fail to capture either the considered moral judgments or the moral principles of those they survey and so fail to contribute to the moral theory they seek to construct.
Rawls defines considered moral judgments as those judgments in which our moral capacities, which he considers analogous to our linguistic capacities, are “most likely to be displayed without distortion”--e.g. those offered without hesitation, given without strong emotions like fear, and made in the absence of conflicting interests (Rawls [3] p.47). The distinction between considered judgments and judgments generally is important. When constructing a moral theory for a particular community—for instance, the patient community—we want to use only those judgments that reflect the respondents’ real moral sensibilities, and not those stemming from superficial prejudices or their mood on the day they happen to respond. This raises two important questions, however, for researchers, like Joffe et al., using the reflective equilibrium: (1) precisely how considered do considered judgments have to be if they are to count, and, more practically, (2) how can a researcher know whether he or she is collecting them (i.e. what survey method, if any, is appropriate for the task)? While it is difficult to give a positive answer to these questions (and I will not attempt to do so here), some survey methods, such as the mailed questionnaires Joffe et al. use, seem particularly inadequate. Rawls suggests certain external conditions favor the formation of considered judgments: “the person making the [considered moral] judgment is presumed…to have the ability, the opportunity and the desire to reach a correct decision (or at least, not the desire not to)”(Rawls [3], p.48). Very likely, however, many of Joffe et al.’s respondents lacked the necessary ability, opportunity, or desire to reflect on their moral judgments when responding to the questionnaire they received in the mail. Furthermore, even if a number of patients did offer legitimate considered judgments, there is no way to distinguish these from those made by respondents’ who lacked the requisite ability or desire. While the size of Joffe et al.’s study is of value for its ability to more accurately reflect a population’s response to its survey questions, because of the practical limitations that come with its size, the study falls short of capturing patients’ considered moral judgments.
Any empirical approach, like Joffe et al.’s, using reflective equilibrium faces a second challenge: why do we want peoples’ considered moral judgments to influence our ethical theories in the first place? In his influential critique of reflective equilibrium, DW Haslett writes, “given the wide differences between people’s considered moral judgments, and given that these differences are, as we know, largely just a reflection of differences in upbringing, culture, religion, and so on, it would appear that, far from having a reason for giving people’s considered moral judgments initial credibility, we have instead a reason for initial skepticism”.[4]
If moral judgments are liable to reflect superficial prejudices, one could argue, considered moral judgments are liable to reflect deep-seated ones. Surely this prejudice is something ethicists would like to overcome, not codify. While I do no think this challenge is insurmountable, [see note 2] it does demand that researchers justify the inclusion of considered judgments in ethical theory before using the method of reflective equilibrium. Joffe et al. have failed to do this.
Joffe et al.’s study is susceptible to a second line of critique. Even if the study’s use of mailed surveys is appropriate, the study fails to capture either patients’ considered judgments or principles, because, put simply, it doesn’t ask for considered judgments or principles. Instead, it asks patients whether providers respected their person or respected their autonomy, and then tests patients’ responses to these questions against whether they report being satisfied with their care. If a provider’s acting with respect for persons is a better predictor of patient satisfaction than her acting with respect for autonomy, Joffe et al. conclude that the principle of respect for persons should be assigned as much importance ethically speaking as the principle of respect for autonomy. As should be clear, this conclusion does not follow from Rawls’s conception of how one constructs a moral theory. In a Rawlsian view .[see note 3] , a moral theory requires knowing which principles patients hold, not whether those principles are associated with patient satisfaction. Joffe et al. seem to be operating with an underlying utilitarian assumption to the effect that what we ought to do ethically speaking is whatever will lead to the greatest patient satisfaction. Though there may be reasons for accepting this utilitarian assumption (which Joffe et al. do not provide), certainly there are others for rejecting it. For instance, though patient satisfaction may give a hospital a very good reason to change a policy, we probably do not want to say this reason is a good ethical reason. It is just good business sense. This is an especially important point given the principles that Joffe et al. evaluate. Respect for autonomy and respect for persons are traditionally viewed deontologically--that is it terms of duties or rights, which are valued for their own sake rather than the consequences (e.g. patient satisfaction) that they produce. In any case, these utility considerations take us far from patients’ actual moral views, the very things Joffe et al., by invoking Rawls’s reflective equilibrium, propose to capture.
Lastly, there is a question of their instrument’s validity. As I have been arguing, Joffe et al. claim to assess whether patients are treated according to the principles of respect for autonomy and respect for persons. Yet, their single item assessing respect for autonomy - the question, "do you feel you had your say?" - does not do the principle justice. The principle of autonomy not only requires that the health care provider ask the patient for his opinion, but also that she act on the patient’s opinion. Their instruments are similarly inadequate for the principle of respect for persons, which, they suggest, includes "autonomy, fidelity, veracity, avoiding killing, and justice" as well as "respect for the body, respect for family, respect for community, respect for culture, respect for the moral value (dignity of the individual), and respect for the personal narrative"(104). How are we to know whether patients had all or any of these in mind when they answered the question, “did you feel like you were treated with respect and dignity while you were in the hospital?” Joffe et al. acknowledge that these ethical concepts are a bit unwieldy for a survey of manageable length. However, these practical considerations should be used not only to excuse the study but also to question its ability to clarify the ethical concepts it claims to assess. They should prod us to ask, regardless of the survey’s scale and the limitations its size produces, does this survey really address what we mean by the principles of respect for autonomy and respect for persons?
With any empirical study in bioethics, there is a gap between the empirical hypothesizes the study confirms and the normative conclusions its authors would like to draw from it. In their article Joffe et al. hoped to bridge this gap by invoking Rawls’s notion of the reflective equilibrium. As I have explored, however, Joffe et al.’s study does not contribute to either side of the reflective equilibrium they imply, and, thus, they fail to demonstrate how their findings challenge the centrality of autonomy and shared decision-making in bioethics.
Joffe et al.’s failures are instructive, however, in so far as they suggest how we might better bridge research and theory. The use of the reflective equilibrium in empirical research has promise, provided researchers are clear about:
(1) how to define considered moral judgments and/or principles,
(2) how their methodology capture these judgments and/or principles reliably,
(3) how the inclusion of considered moral judgments strengthens rather than weakens bioethical theory, and
(4) how their instruments are valid for the judgments or principles they mean to assess.
In addition, empirical research can contribute to bioethics by questioning the assumptions implicit or explicit in our normative views. Joffe et al. try to do just this when they argue that patients’ desire to delegate decision-making challenges the mandatory autonomy view, in the introduction of their paper ([1] p.103). However, if empirical findings are to defeat a particular normative principle, the assumption those findings challenge must be logically necessary for our holding that principle. For instance, without showing patients’ desiring autonomy is necessary for our holding the mandatory autonomy view, the studies that Joffe et al. cite, even if valid, can be interpreted variously as devaluing the mandatory autonomy view or as recommending that we better educate patients on the value of autonomy. This normative question cannot be settled empirically.
Empirical researchers have the potential to contribute substantially to bioethics, but their work needs the kind of philosophical and empirical rigor that comes from truly interdisciplinary collaboration and must be informed by a careful reflection on the proper relationship between descriptive and normative ethics (Sulmasy and Sugarman).[4] Joffe et al. take us part of the way down that path. An exciting research itinerary lies ahead.
References
(1) Joffe S, Manocchia M, Weeks J C, Cleary P D. What do patients value in their hospital care? An empirical perspective on autonomy centred bioethics. J Med Ethics 2003; 29:103-108.
(2) Rawls J. The independence of moral theory. In: Freeman S, editor. Collected papers / John Rawls. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999. p.286-302.
(3) Rawls J. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971.
(4) Haslett DW. What is wrong with reflective equilibria? The Philosophical Quarterly 1987; 36(148):305-311.
(5) Sulmasy DP, Sugarman J. “The many methods of medical ethics (or, thirteen ways of looking at a blackbird).” In: Sugarman J, Sulmasy DP, editors. Methods in Medical Ethics. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2001.
(6) Delden JJM, Thiel GJMW. Reflective equilibrium as a normative-empirical model in bioethics. In: Burg W, Willligenburg T, editors. Reflective equilibrium: essays in honour of Robert Heeger. Dodrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998. p. 251-259.
(7) Rawls J. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.
Notes
Note 1:
Joffe et al. also evaluate whether patients’ reporting they had confidence and trust in their health care providers significantly predicted whether they would recommend their hospital to others. For simplicity’s sake, I only address Joffe et al.’s treatment of the respect for persons and the respect for autonomy principles in this response.
Note 2:
See, for instance, Delden and Theil,[6] in which the authors convincingly argue that a reflective equilibrium-like methodology may be valuable for capturing the norms of health care providers and that knowledge of these norms may guide individual providers.
Note 3:
I say “a Rawlsian view” rather than “Rawls’s view” because in his Theory of Justice Rawls advocates balancing a single person’s considered moral judgments (e.g. Rawls’s or his reader’s) with a single person’s moral principles (Rawls [3]p.50). Although he later gestures towards reflective equilibrium a an exercise that involves the considered moral judgments of others (Rawls [7], p.8), it is probably safest to say “Rawslian.”
Since the 50s,with the work of Guillan and Mollaret, there has been a
preoccupation with the point of no return in brain activity;
these French authors choose the expression “coma depassé”. After the first
and ethical heart transplantation in South Africa, performed by
the Barnard brothers, the medical world was suddenly thrown into a debate about the definition of death. The
Harvard ad hoc Committee was...
Since the 50s,with the work of Guillan and Mollaret, there has been a
preoccupation with the point of no return in brain activity;
these French authors choose the expression “coma depassé”. After the first
and ethical heart transplantation in South Africa, performed by
the Barnard brothers, the medical world was suddenly thrown into a debate about the definition of death. The
Harvard ad hoc Committee was the first to put the neurological and ethical
issues in a more traditional way, considering the definition of brain
death as death itself. At present, we have a lot of protocols to
determine brain death, and many ancillary
examinations to confirm the clinical diagnosis, from the old EEG criteria of the Harvard committee to the up-to-date flow and metabolic
analyses existing today, such as transcranial Doppler examination, evoked
potentials, SPECT, angio-MR, and so. There is strong evidence in the medical
literature to support the definition of brain death as the death itself, using the protocols for both transplanted and non-transplanted cases. Of course, we have an ethical problem at this point, but to use only heart criteria to indicate death is to refuse to acknowledge the lack of activity in the central nervous system as the mark of death. The initial definition
of brain death is modified to brainstem death by Christopher Pallis and,
more recently, to the concept of whole brain death, as pointed out by Calixto
Machado. With appropriate measures and trained professionals,
brain death criteria vary little throughout the world, as a recent paper by Eeelco Widjics shows. All of the research that has been carried out by
neurologists, intensivists, anaesthetists, and participants in organ transplantation teams, should make us certain that lack of brain function is the point of no return.
Reintroducing the heart into the definition of death is regressive,
provides no more ethical standard than the brain criteria, and could promote (again) interminable discussions of death, with no practical and
bioethical advantage. This would be regressive thinking and could overshadow more than 30 years of research by groups throughout the world in this field.
Dr. Fessler discusses in detail the implications of starvation induced psychological changes for the ethical treatment of hunger strikers,[1] but cannot bring himself in his conclusions to deviate from respecting the competent hunger striker's decision to continue to fast until death. This is clearly also the virtually unanimous Western ethical consensus, giving autonomy the priority over life.
Dr. Fessler discusses in detail the implications of starvation induced psychological changes for the ethical treatment of hunger strikers,[1] but cannot bring himself in his conclusions to deviate from respecting the competent hunger striker's decision to continue to fast until death. This is clearly also the virtually unanimous Western ethical consensus, giving autonomy the priority over life.
In another publication [2] I reported a contrary decision of an Israeli district court in the case of a hunger striking prisoner which stated categorically that when human life conflicts with human dignity the preservation of life takes precedence. In this case, as well as others, including one cited in the International Red Cross Committee document on the subject, the prisoner, after being force-fed, expressed his gratitude at his life having been saved against his expressed opposition. This is not infrequently the case. Hunger strikers who are competent by all standard criteria may often be trapped into continuing onto death by their own rhetoric and pride, as well as by their embarrassment from their political compatriots. When force-fed they can retain their pride and conviction at not having capitulated- and, as a bonus, keep their lives as well, enabling them to use their talents in their continuing struggle for their cause. It is sad that the rigid adherence to the value of autonomy at all costs has caused the death of so many young and often idealistic young people.
References
(1) Fessler DMT. The implications of starvation induced psychological changes for the ethical treatment of hunger strikers. J Med Ethics 2003;29:243-247.
(2) Glick SM. Unlimited human autonomy - a cultural bias?
N Engl J Med 1997 Mar 27;336(13):954-6.
Gebhardt in his brief report pleads for patient organisations to establish databanks on medical complications. Given the references (e.g. to a journalist article by Paans entitled “Medical errors to be kept secret”) and the lack of argumentation, there is substantial danger of misinterpretation of the current situation, which in turn may frustrate the process of increased transparency. We would therefore li...
Gebhardt in his brief report pleads for patient organisations to establish databanks on medical complications. Given the references (e.g. to a journalist article by Paans entitled “Medical errors to be kept secret”) and the lack of argumentation, there is substantial danger of misinterpretation of the current situation, which in turn may frustrate the process of increased transparency. We would therefore like to respond to this by giving background information and reasons for some of the choices that were made with respect to the registry of complications mentioned by Gebhardt.
First, a distinction needs to be made between an error and an adverse outcome, which is often confused. Given the referral of Gebhardt to the journalist article in which the same registry of adverse outcomes is discussed, but with the title referring to errors, both Gebhardt and the journalist think of errors and adverse outcomes to be the same thing. However, an error refers to the process in which something has gone wrong, to a sub-standard performance, regardless of the outcome. It has been explained by others that such a judgement may have a degree of subjectivity.[1] An adverse outcome refers to the outcome which is unwanted, but which not necessarily implies that an error has been made. This is why the term ‘adverse outcomes’ is used rather than the term ‘complications’, since the latter term is often confused with an error being made. The registration of medical complications that Gebhardt refers to, is a registration of surgical adverse outcomes, guided by an unambiguous definition of the term “adverse outcome”, of which only a small percentage is related to errors. Furthermore, some errors will be missed in this registration, i.e. errors which have not lead to adverse outcomes.
Secondly, with respect to the confidentiality, this is relevant in particular for the initial years of such a registry in which it is thoroughly tested and the accuracy of the registration may vary widely between participants. Nothing is gained by false-positive signals with respect to high adverse outcome incidences in certain hospitals, except perhaps by flashing headlines in news papers. In this respect one may compare the development of such a national registry to the development of a new drug, in which case no one argues confidentiality and thorough testing until proven safe. Moreover, a pharmaceutical company will probably be sued if it markets a new drug without proper research. It is intended that after this first period, national adverse outcome data will become available to the public with respect to probabilities on an adverse outcome, given certain types of surgery.
Finally, what does the patient want? (see Box 1)
Box 1
Patients need information to make a well informed choice
What is a good doctor and what is a good
hospital? This simple question is not easy to get answered for individual
patients who need a good diagnosis and the best treatment. The NPCF (Dutch
Federation of Patients and Consumer Organisations) and its member
organisations have published several consumer guides for specific diseases
to help patients to find their way in the labyrinth of the health care
system. They have experienced many difficulties in getting access to
relevant information of doctors organisations and insurance companies.
Therefore the NPCF wants to cooperate with these organisations to create
consumer information, based on the important and relevant data that are
available. A joint project for a databank on best practices will start in
September.
Patients are not interested in black
lists of doctors and malpractices but they prefer good and best practices
to make a well informed choice for a doctor or hospital. They need
consumer information on objective parameters like the risk on infections
in a hospital, the specific skills of a doctor, how many patients with
this specific disease a doctor treats a year etc. Patients also like to
receive subjective information on a specific hospital or doctor: how is
the communication between a doctor and his patients, does the team give
enough information and support when needed etc. This experience based
information is often available among patients organisations.
The NPCF has chosen to work together with
organisations of health care providers and insurance companies to use
parts of their databanks as a basis for consumer information. A task of
the NPCF is to translate the data to consumer information that meets the
needs of the patients, based on research and experiences of patients.
Joint efforts are needed to make this
important information accessible for doctors and patients!
Dr Iris van Bennekom, Director NPCF
International research has shown that patients do not use public information on performance of hospitals or doctors for their choice of treatment or hospital, among other because they do not understand and do not trust these data. This also applies to adverse outcome data. For the interpretation of hospital specific adverse outcome incidences it is vital to know the context, since e.g. older, sicker and more complex patients have higher probabilities on adverse outcomes.[2] It is therefore vital that a reliable registry is established that can be trusted and understood both by medical professionals and the public. For this reason, the Association of Surgeons of the Netherlands and the Dutch Federation of Patients and Consumer Organisations (NPCF) collaborate with respect to the national surgical adverse outcome registry, in particular to produce information that is relevant for patients with respect to treatment and hospital choices. Supported by international literature, the NPCF holds the view that patients are not primarily interested in adverse outcome data, since patients are aware that they need the context to be able to interpret these data. Patients are more interested in experience of doctors or hospitals to treat certain disease or to perform certain operations, since they want the question answered ‘What is the best place to go for this type of problem?’. That this doctor or hospital will probably have a high adverse outcome record is not relevant, since it may well be explained by the complex patients that are referred to more experienced doctors. As argued in a previous paper,[3] it is essential that there is an increased and mutual trust between the medical profession and patients’ organisation, that supports a combined effort to improve the quality and availability of patient information. Such initiatives will benefit both patients and doctors, and are too important to be frustrated by references to “powers that must be kept under control”.
Dr PJ Marang- van de Mheen
Epidemiologist
Association of Surgeons in the Netherlands
Professor Dr J Kievit
Surgeon and Head of Department of Medical Decision Making
Leiden University Medical Centre
References
(1) Hayward RA, Hofer TP. Estimating hospital deaths due to medical errors: preventability is in the eye of the reviewer. JAMA 2001;286(4):415-420.
(2) Kievit J. Regarding covering-up: a database for registration of adverse outcomes (in Dutch). Med Contact 2001;56(48):1777-1779.
(3) Marshall MN, Shekelle PG, Leatherman S, Brook RH. The public release of performance data. What do we expect to gain? A review of the evidence. JAMA 2000;283:1866-74.
Arthur Schafer has a good point in regards to the
commercialization of IP, but how can anyone agree
with such a paranoid and polorazing view of the drug
companies. Banning them completely would only
create an underground of business transactions. At
least with gifts to the Universities we know who and
where the money is dispersed and for what.
It is time the public became more involved in th...
Arthur Schafer has a good point in regards to the
commercialization of IP, but how can anyone agree
with such a paranoid and polorazing view of the drug
companies. Banning them completely would only
create an underground of business transactions. At
least with gifts to the Universities we know who and
where the money is dispersed and for what.
It is time the public became more involved in this
discussion and that is why we are having a Conference
November 4-5, in Toronto to discuss the Scientist
as Entrepreneur, with Dr Nancy Olivieri. This is
not a controversy that is going to go away and I
applaud Professor Schafer for not pretending that it
doesn't exist.
JME is to be congratulated for offering the important Olivieri
Symposium free of charge on a pre-publication basis. The Olivieri and
Healy affairs occurred at one university, in one province. Based on the
articles by Arthur Schafer, Gordon DuVal, and Lorraine Ferris and
colleagues, non-Canadian readers might underestimate the scope of the
crisis confronting research ethics review in Canadian uni...
JME is to be congratulated for offering the important Olivieri
Symposium free of charge on a pre-publication basis. The Olivieri and
Healy affairs occurred at one university, in one province. Based on the
articles by Arthur Schafer, Gordon DuVal, and Lorraine Ferris and
colleagues, non-Canadian readers might underestimate the scope of the
crisis confronting research ethics review in Canadian universities and
hospitals. I would like to expand on two institutional aspects of that
crisis, with primary reference to Ontario (Canada's largest province, the
one with which I am most familiar, and the one to which the articles in
the symposium refer). I have no reason to believe that the situation
elsewhere is either better or worse.
If implemented, Gordon DuVal's proposal that REBs review many aspects
of research contracts before they are approved by universities and
hospitals would represent a major change for the better. However, his
belief that REBs are "independent" bodies misses a crucial point. McDonald
[1] has pointed out that 'university REBs generally report to the offices
that promote research.' In many universities, the overwhelming majority
of REB members are employees of the university or its affiliated
hospitals; in one case, at least, they are appointed directly by the
president of the university. Remarkably, no systematic published research
on this point appears to exist, or to be in progress. Neither does the
Tri-Council Statement of Principles, the federal granting councils' non-
binding guidelines for REBs, include any requirements that address the
independence of REB members. Under these circumstances, it is probably
difficult for REBs to take positions, such as asking to scrutinize
contractual arrangements for sponsored research, that will seriously
impede their institutions' quest for research funding. An REB taking this
position would also not be able to find any specific support for such an
interpretation of its mandate in the Tri-Council Statement. Given the
meagre resources normally available for REB activities, an REB wishing
(for instance) to commission a legal opinion on this point would probably
have to take up a collection among its members, or hold a bake sale.
Ethical concerns arising from the shift to private research funding
in universities as a consequence of (policy-induced) scarcity of public
funds are now generally acknowledged. Canadian hospitals confront a
similar situation, and the tradeoffs they make in response are even less
visible than those made by universities. In Ontario, hospitals can be
(and have been) taken over by provincially appointed trustees for failure
to balance their budgets,[2] but no comparable mechanism exists for
scrutiny either of the ethical short-cuts that may have been taken in the
interests of raising revenue, or of what happens to patient care once
"business development" becomes a priority. Lorraine Ferris and her
colleagues concede that hospital-based researchers may lack even the
minimal protections against reprisal that are available in the university
setting when ethics collide with institutional (read: financial)
priorities. The CEO of Toronto's University Health Network, the hospital
complex affiliated with the University of Toronto, recently stated in the
context of a shortage of resources for pain care that: 'We decided that
patient need, in a broad context, wasn't one of our criteria in deciding
priorities.'[3] This is suggestive of a culture in which some patients
have become more important than others, based inter alia on their value as
clinical trial participants, suppliers of scientifically interesting
biological materials, or sources of data that can then be "warehoused" for
purposes of subsequent research.
Under these circumstances, it is hard not to be sceptical about
proposals for improvements in the governance of research that fail to
incorporate genuinely independent oversight, meaningful sanctions for
misconduct, and a high level of transparency. On this last point, it
should be noted that Ontario's hospitals and universities are both exempt
from even the weak public disclosure requirements imposed on other public
sector agencies by provincial freedom of information legislation.
References
(1) McDonald M. Canadian governance of health research involving
human subjects: is anybody minding the store? Health Law Journal 2001;9:1-22.
(2) Heinz C. Government Taking Back Control of Public
Hospitals. Hospital News 2002;15(12),December:12,14.
(3) Papp L. Patients' torment ignored. Toronto Star 2003; June 20.
Firstly, I have a great deal of admiration for this book, which provides much stimulating and thoughtful debate. As such, the
book invites a certain amount of friendly criticism from a non-academic perspective.
What is significantly missing is any inclusion of the 'service users' authentic voice or information for students on the...
Firstly, I have a great deal of admiration for this book, which provides much stimulating and thoughtful debate. As such, the
book invites a certain amount of friendly criticism from a non-academic perspective.
What is significantly missing is any inclusion of the 'service users' authentic voice or information for students on the
'user/survivor' movement across UK and Europe at least. The history of the movement should by now be part of any mental
health course but this is still rare. There is concern about using the 'case histories' without consent even where they are
anonymised - this just pays lip service to rights which can so easily be sacrificed to expediency, including for publications. It
is important though the practice reveals an unacceptable imbalance of power in the relationship between health service users
and researchers etc. which is not addressed or highlighted for students. With only intellectual debate about such issues the
reality for those on the receiving end can be missed. Another significant absence is input from any non-white European
contributors - in a modern Uk this is a serious omission. It would also have been good to see some of the abuses in psychiatry
identified as having taken place in UK as well as in other countries such as Russia. The area of research invites debate as the
author claims too much intrusion or hold ups by perhaps unqualified LRECs is limiting devlopment - whereas lack of knowledge
is a problem sometimes proper checks are worth the wait unless more situations Alderheys are to happen. Once involved in an
area it can come to seem all important - which is why an inclusive debate about any aspect of healthcare is vital. This book
stimulates that in many ways but does not include a wide enough inclusion of views in my mind,to be wholly in agreement of
it's success - A follow up would be good. It is one I would want students to read though.
As a group of Nephrologists with a lively interest in ethical
problems and involved in an educational campaign on dialysis and
transplantation, we read with great pleasure the pragmatic and touching
editorial of HE Emson;[1] as the senior of the group, I (GBP) had the
occasion to watch the moment when the soul departs from the body; without
the fear of being “unscientific”, I agree with Dr Emson that whe...
As a group of Nephrologists with a lively interest in ethical
problems and involved in an educational campaign on dialysis and
transplantation, we read with great pleasure the pragmatic and touching
editorial of HE Emson;[1] as the senior of the group, I (GBP) had the
occasion to watch the moment when the soul departs from the body; without
the fear of being “unscientific”, I agree with Dr Emson that wherever the
soul goes, the body remains as an empty shell. The sadness of departure is
enhanced by the fact that we usually know, often in friendly terms, most
of the persons we see in the moment of end of life. At the meantime, we
share with our dialysis patients the anxious wait for a renal graft,
giving back freedom and a better, and hopefully longer life.
While we agree with the Author that our bodies should be considered
as a valuable loan from the biomass, we do not agree with the opinion that
the lack of donation is linked to the family attention on a dead body.
In our country, Italy, about one third of the potential donors are
“wasted”, going directly under the ground to produce corn or flowers, due
to the family opposition to organ donation.[2] The cult for the dead
body, the lack of trust in the Health Care System, the misconceptions on
brain death were all considered as potential explanations of this pattern.
As dr Emson says, the comments and theorizations are often performed by
philosophy experts, not directly involved in the care of the patients, nor
in running educational programs.
In the last three years, in the context of the activities of the post
graduate school of Nephrology, we run an educational campaign in Torino,
an industrial northern Italian city with about 900,000 inhabitants,
progressively involving all the high schools of the city (last two years
of high school: median students’ age 17 and 18 years).
In 2001-2002, 1676 anonymous questionnaires on different aspects of
dialysis, transplantation and organ donation were gathered from 14
schools. Students’ opinions were clearly in favour of living kidney
donation: 78.2% would donate a kidney to a close relative or partner
needing it, witnessing the diffuse knowledge that life with a kidney
transplant is highly preferable than life with dialysis.
However, the answers on cadaveric donation were sharply different. The
question, built as a “collage” of sentences from the newspapers was: “a
dear person of your family is in the emergency room; you do not know
his/her opinion on organ donation; the doctor says this he/she is brain
dead (the heart is still beating with the help of a machine); do you give
the consent to organ donation?” the answers were almost evenly divided
among yes (35.5%), not (30%), I dont’ know (34.5%).
The optional comments, recorded in about half of the questionnaires
(blank: 44.4 %) identify in the impossibility of deciding for somebody
else (20.5%) and in the fear of causing the “real death” of the beloved
person (19.9%) the main reasons for denying consent, followed by the lack
of trust in the medical class (3.2%).
None of the students mentioned the insult on the dead body nor gave
religious motivations; a minority (5.4%) considered organ transplantation
an “unnatural” procedure.
From our data, we suggest that, at least in our setting, the focus
for increasing organ donation should be on giving exhaustive information
on life (and on end of life), clarifying the concept of brain death, the
aims and itineraries of transplantation, more then on fighting with
prejudices on death.
Our direct involvement, as physicians, in educational campaigns may
not only give a valuable occasion to get in touch with the general
population, but also, as Dr Emson states, to fill the gap between the
large number of people who favour organ donation and the small proportion
who do anything about it.
References
(1) Emson HE. It is immoral to require consent for cadaver organ donation. J Med Ethics 2003;29:125-127.
Dear Editor
the concept of brain death (BD) refers to two different but strictly related conditions: the death of the brain ("the irreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem"[1]) and the patient's death certified by neurological criteria.
In his letter, C. Levyman strongly supports both aspects of the concept. Actually, even if nobody challenges the fact the BD i...
Dear Editor
The comments of Marang and Kievit are interesting, but are they relevant?[1]
I fear not, or at best only in part. The authors have failed to answer the question, which I raised and its implication. Therefore I will try to do this myself.
1. Are medical doctors required to present medical information to a judge, if there is a likelihood that the information or evidence can be used in cour...
Dear Editor
In the Journal of Medical Ethics, Joffe et al. recently published an article titled:
What do patients value in their hospital care? An empirical perspective on autonomy centred bioethic [1]
This empirical study evaluates whether patients’ willingness to recommend their hospital to others is more strongly associated with their belief that they were treated with...
Dear Editor
Since the 50s,with the work of Guillan and Mollaret, there has been a preoccupation with the point of no return in brain activity; these French authors choose the expression “coma depassé”. After the first and ethical heart transplantation in South Africa, performed by the Barnard brothers, the medical world was suddenly thrown into a debate about the definition of death. The Harvard ad hoc Committee was...
Dear Editor
Dr. Fessler discusses in detail the implications of starvation induced psychological changes for the ethical treatment of hunger strikers,[1] but cannot bring himself in his conclusions to deviate from respecting the competent hunger striker's decision to continue to fast until death. This is clearly also the virtually unanimous Western ethical consensus, giving autonomy the priority over life.
In a...
Dear Editor
Gebhardt in his brief report pleads for patient organisations to establish databanks on medical complications. Given the references (e.g. to a journalist article by Paans entitled “Medical errors to be kept secret”) and the lack of argumentation, there is substantial danger of misinterpretation of the current situation, which in turn may frustrate the process of increased transparency. We would therefore li...
Dear Editor
Arthur Schafer has a good point in regards to the commercialization of IP, but how can anyone agree with such a paranoid and polorazing view of the drug companies. Banning them completely would only create an underground of business transactions. At least with gifts to the Universities we know who and where the money is dispersed and for what.
It is time the public became more involved in th...
Dear Editor
JME is to be congratulated for offering the important Olivieri Symposium free of charge on a pre-publication basis. The Olivieri and Healy affairs occurred at one university, in one province. Based on the articles by Arthur Schafer, Gordon DuVal, and Lorraine Ferris and colleagues, non-Canadian readers might underestimate the scope of the crisis confronting research ethics review in Canadian uni...
Dear Editor
Firstly, I have a great deal of admiration for this book, which provides much stimulating and thoughtful debate. As such, the book invites a certain amount of friendly criticism from a non-academic perspective.
What is significantly missing is any inclusion of the 'service users' authentic voice or information for students on the...
Dear Editor
As a group of Nephrologists with a lively interest in ethical problems and involved in an educational campaign on dialysis and transplantation, we read with great pleasure the pragmatic and touching editorial of HE Emson;[1] as the senior of the group, I (GBP) had the occasion to watch the moment when the soul departs from the body; without the fear of being “unscientific”, I agree with Dr Emson that whe...
Pages