Dr. Biegler concludes that patient consent to a DNR order should be
required [1]. He rightly locates the reason for that ethical demand in
the principle of autonomy. If autonomy means anything, it must mean a
right to be involved in decisions about one’s own survival. It is also
correct to say that the law of consent, at least in common law
jurisdictions, is built on the philosophical foundation of au...
Dr. Biegler concludes that patient consent to a DNR order should be
required [1]. He rightly locates the reason for that ethical demand in
the principle of autonomy. If autonomy means anything, it must mean a
right to be involved in decisions about one’s own survival. It is also
correct to say that the law of consent, at least in common law
jurisdictions, is built on the philosophical foundation of autonomy [2].
Dr. Biegler seems to imply that consistent application of the principle of
autonomy would require the law of consent to agree with his conclusion
about DNR orders. But the law of consent is not the only law relevant to
the question of the requirement of consent to a DNR order. Also engaged is
the more general law governing a doctor’s duty to his patient. This is
painfully dislocated from the law of consent. Broadly, in UK law at least,
a doctor can choose when to assume a duty [3]. If he chooses to assume
that duty, the law of negligence swings into play and says what he has to
do in order to discharge it properly. But at almost any time the doctor
can wash his hands of the patient. That washing might get a doctor into
trouble with his employers or with the GMC: it will not get him into
trouble with the law of tort. The law of tort will not draft conditions of
employment.
If a doctor decides to assume a duty, the law tends to describe his
obligations in negative terms. It tells him that he must not do certain
things. Even when condemning commissions it uses negative language: such
and such a commission would amount to a dereliction of duty. Having been
brought up in the context of negligence, the law is almost totally
inarticulate in its discussion of positive duties. There is only one
arguable example of a positive duty: the duty to act in the best interests
of a patient who is unable to consent to the proposed treatment. The
deployment of the Bolam test [4] in ascertaining the patient's "best
interests" and determining the compliance of a doctor’s actions with those
"best interests", transmutes even this duty into something akin to the
ordinary obligation of not being a negligent doctor.
The relevance of the "best interests" criterion to the question of
consent to a DNR order is interesting and moot. At the time Dr. Biegler
says the consent should be taken, the patient is of course conscious and
presumably competent. That would suggest that no "best interests"
considerations arise at all. But at the moment when any resuscitation
attempt would occur, the patient would be unconscious. Then, conventional
legal wisdom would say, the only relevant consideration is that of "best
interests".
All this cannot cloak the legal reality. The corollary of Dr.
Biegler’s proposal is that a patient could require a doctor to resuscitate
him. (If Dr. Biegler would not go this far, then the requirement he is
talking about is not a requirement to obtain a patient’s consent to DNR at
all, but an obligation simply to discuss the issue, which is a very
different matter.) This would require radical exceptions to be made to
three fundamental legal principles. First: a patient would,
unprecedentedly in the law of tort, have to be able to force a doctor to
enter into a doctor-patient relationship and thereby assume a duty.
Second, the patient would have to be able to force the doctor to do a
positive act. And third, the doctor would have to be required to do
something to an unconscious patient which he did not believe was in the
patient’s best interests.
Those principles are there for a number of good reasons. If they are
eroded, there may be damage to the law a long way from the ICU.
References
(1) Biegler P. Should patient consent be required to write a do not
resucitate order? J Med Ethics 2003; 29: 359-363
(2) See, for example, Sidaway v Board of Governors of Bethlem Royal
Hospital [1985] 1 AC 171, per Lord Scarman at 182; and Airedale NHS Trust
v Bland [1993] AC 789, per Lord Goff at 864 and Lord Mustill at 891.
3. Jones v Manchester Corporation [1952] QB 852; Cassidy v Ministry
of Health [1951] 2 KB 343; Capital and Counties plc v Hampshire County
Council [1997] 2 All ER 865
5. See F v West Berkshire Health Authority [1990] 2 AC 1; Re SL
(adult patient) (medical treatment) [2000] 1 FCR 361: Re A (medical
treatment: male sterilization) [2000] 1 FCR 193
Whilst I am an advocate for dialogue and mutual understanding and
indeed have written on the possible acceptance of emergency contraception
in instances of rape, I find this article by L. Bovens rather disturbing
and at most insulting to the general Catholic population. Although he uses
the term pro-life, this can only be an emotive attempt, rather than
rational argumentation, since 'pro-lifers' have b...
Whilst I am an advocate for dialogue and mutual understanding and
indeed have written on the possible acceptance of emergency contraception
in instances of rape, I find this article by L. Bovens rather disturbing
and at most insulting to the general Catholic population. Although he uses
the term pro-life, this can only be an emotive attempt, rather than
rational argumentation, since 'pro-lifers' have been associated with hard-
line fundamentalists - which indeed in itself is unfortunate.
Catholics do sometimes complain that using the rhythm method is in a
sense hypocritical and since the intent is the same, then why not use oral
contraception. They do so however in a certain aptitude of ignorance of
the pharmacodynamics and pharmacokinetics of the drug. Oral contraception
is intent merely on stopping the reproductive function, period. It has
also been known to be abortifacient, especially when women are given the
advice to take two pills the next day after a day in which they would have
missed out; and even three pills if they forget taking it for two days.
Perhaps there is an omission of the informed consent process on the part
of the prescribers in this process.
The rhythm method is simply a method by which couples are careful
when the woman is ovulating. This can be used both for the intent of
having babies or for not having them. I will restrict myself to the
Catholic perspective. Being Catholics means being united as a couple. This
unity must be seen in the perspective of trinitarian theology which speaks
of kenosis and perichoresis. The latter is the emptying of oneself; the
former is the making oneself 'one' with the other. This does not translate
that therefore the couple, being one, cannot have a say in God's plan on
planning their family. Where would freedom be if this were not so?
Philosophically however it is even more problematic to think that
people cannot have a say by controlling their reproductive life.
Technically we can spend our whole life in bed trying to have babies,
since every moment that passes is an opportunity 'lost'. Indeed this in
itself is a reductio ad absurdum of Boven's argumentation, I am afraid.
One has also to consider the reasons chosen for family planning. Not
all may be justified and therefore the morality of natural family planning
lies in this non-manifest agenda rather than solely in the act. Besides
this there is the whole concept of one being a natural method which is
inherent in human nature and understanding of its own physiology. The
other is based on a physical barrier, intent on altering one's physiology
and nature. This may be fine for many; it does not translate into being a
moral falsehood for those who believe in the unity and agape of marriage.
Erin and Harris [1] suggest that we need a regulated market in
live donor organs to make good the shortfall in organs available for
transplantation. However, the example of the third world shows that to
sell a kidney is virtually always an act of desperation when other
options for raising money are exhausted, for example Goyal et al.[2] reported that 96% of participants in their survey of kidney...
Erin and Harris [1] suggest that we need a regulated market in
live donor organs to make good the shortfall in organs available for
transplantation. However, the example of the third world shows that to
sell a kidney is virtually always an act of desperation when other
options for raising money are exhausted, for example Goyal et al.[2] reported that 96% of participants in their survey of kidney sellers in
India did it to repay debt. In these circumstances there would have to
be
grave concerns that any potential sellers could not be freely
consenting,
as they would effectively be being coerced by their social
circumstances. In addition, recent scandals in the financial services industry should
remind us that abuses can occur even in regulated, first world, markets.
References
(1) Erin CA, Harris J. An ethical market in organs J Med Ethics 2003;29:137-8.
(2) Goyal M, Mehta RL, Schneiderman LJ, Sehgal AR. (2002) The Economic
and Health Consequences of selling a kidney in India. Journal of the
American Medical Association (JAMA). 2nd Oct 2002. 288 (13) 1589 - 93.
This article on Reproductive Ethics is unfortunate in a number of
respects,
and while I would not identify with the pro-life movement of the article,
I feel
it necessary to respond from the standpoint of a proponent of the modern
Billings Ovulation Method of Natural Family Planning (NFP).
NFP Methods Bovens seems to choose to reduce all NFP to one approach, the
defi...
This article on Reproductive Ethics is unfortunate in a number of
respects,
and while I would not identify with the pro-life movement of the article,
I feel
it necessary to respond from the standpoint of a proponent of the modern
Billings Ovulation Method of Natural Family Planning (NFP).
NFP Methods Bovens seems to choose to reduce all NFP to one approach, the
definitively
obsolete Rhythm Method. This alone renders the basis of the article’s
moral
extrapolations to all NFP at best inappropriate, and signals that the
“plausible
empirical assumptions” on which much else in the article is based are
inapplicable to current NFP use.
Boven’s second assumption is correct only in the sense that the obsolete
rhythm method was a statistical calculation, and intercourse on days
adjacent
to the required abstinence phase’s limits could in a minority of cases
result in
conception, because that method failed to recognise the natural variation
of
cycles, which almost all current NFP methods do. It is not correct,
however, as
a basis for what follows in the article.
Physiology Boven’s first assumption that 50% of natural human conceptions are
lost is an
often-repeated figure based on problematic research in 1956 (1) using
histological anaysis of hysterectomies where intercourse was encouraged
prior to surgery. The higher figure of 78% often quoted rests on a 1975
analysis (2) of an hypothesis based on a series of weak assumptions.
Animal
studies commonly give percentages in single figures.
Boven’s third assumption is wholly invalid in the light of current
knowledge of
human reproductive physiology. The ovum lasts for about 12 hours, 24 at
most; sperm may last up to 3-5 days with the support of both the
appropriate types of cervical mucus and of the activity of the cervical
crypts.
Any conception is as viable as the next, barring a fatal genetic or
developmental defect; there is no truth to the old “old sperm” or “old
ovum”
speculation, or its “twice as likely to be viable”, “lack resilience” and
“reduced
survival chances” assumption.
Neither is there any truth in the “heightened fertility (HF)” and ‘tail-
end
fertility” idea, with or without further speculative assumptions about
extrapolated comparative embryonic viability based on this innacuracy. A
luteal phase of less than 11 days may be insufficient to sustain a natural
conception, but this is a case for medical intervention. So all that
follows
based on the HF and other assumptions is invalid.
His fourth point of counter-argument depends on the idea that natural
conception could be timed in NFP use for when the endometrium is
inhospitable to an embryo; this is physiological nonsense. The symphony of
ovulation-related events ensures that the endometrium is ready for
implantation until when either the corpus lutem expires or ßHCG is
produced.
It is a complete fallacy to assert, even in regard to the obsolete rhythm
method, that any NFP methods “depend for their successes on massive
embryonic death”.
Natural Ethics, Harris The article fails to acknowledge the distinction between natural loss
and loss
caused by deliberate human intervention; common sense and every criminal
law system recognise the importance of knowledge and intent in human
responsibility; in particular, the fact that accidental deaths happen does
not
justify causing similar deaths.
Bovens adopts Harris’ perspective, that the knowledge that some embryos
will not naturally survive, amounts to convicting any couple then
continuing
to conceive naturally of “destruction” (3) of embryos. This is a thesis
open to
redutio ad absurdum, and rests on Harris’ having dismissed to his
satisfaction the double effect principle patently used universally in
daily life
and medical practice.
Probability Calculus Any mathematical model’s results based on inaccuracies and guesses
are
misleading; the comparative scale of embyonic loss is baseless because the
fundamental assumption in regard to NFP and embryo survival is
unsupported by the evidence.
Alcorn The article’s use of Alcorn is open to question. He proposed an
“infinitesmal”
small proportion (0.01%) of pill-use cycles resulting in a conception lost
due
to pill use, to provide a minimum statistic for purposes of illustration
and
contrast. Bovens takes Alcorn’s minimal estimate and uses it as if it were
fact
in regard to embryo loss on the combined oral contraceptive pill, so that
his
supposed “loss” with use of the rhythm method seems huge by comparison.
What is known is that older formulations of the pill allowed breakthrough
ovulation in 2-10% , (4,5) or 4.7% (6) of cycles, and about 27 cycles per
100
women per year in later studies (7). Progesterone preparations have higher
ovulation rates, and the IUD still higher. Recording or calculating a
‘conception and loss rate’ for these cycles is another matter.
Condom use statistic Any manufacturer would be delighted to be able to claim a 95% use-effectiveness for his condom. 88% is more usually quoted as an average
figure.
“can this argument be blocked?” The first point is in fact valid; the article’s embyonic death
proposition is
untenable, being based on ignorance and error in physiology – sadly not
unique to Bovens.
The second point seems to call abortion an action but the use of an IUD a
form of omission; ensuring that implantation will not occur (to put it
graphically) is not “not providing the right environment for embryonic
growth”.
The third point conflates OCP use and NFP use from a moral standpoint in
continuing the incorrect assumption that NFP is a “mixed” contraceptive
approach involving the loss of embryos.
The fourth point involves the physiological fallacy that a natural
conception
could be timed for when the endometrium would be unsupportive of its
implantation, and a repetition of the mis-application of “the
action/omission
doctrine”.
The conclusion This article is anything but a reductio ad absurdum of anybody’s
cornerstone.
In regard to factual accuracy (8) and undestanding of its bases in NFP and
physiology, it is itself unfortunately based on the absurdum.
Dr Mark Whitty, MSc; Dublin, Ireland.
References
(1) Hertig AT, Rock J, et al: A description of 34 human ova within
the first 17
days of development. AJAnat 98; 435-493, 1956.
(2) Roberts CJ, Lowe CR: Where have all the conceptions gone? Lancet
1;
498-499, March 1 1975.
(3) Harris J: Stem cells, sex and procreation. Camb Q Healthc Eth12,
353-371,
2003; (page 364).
(4) Peel J, Potts M: Textbook of Contraceptive Practice, Cambridge UP
1969.
(6) Van der Vange N: Ovarian activity during low dose oral
contraceptives. In
Chamberlain G ed: Contemporary Obstetrics and Gynaecology, Butterworths
London 1988 pp 315-326.
(7) Grimes DA, Goodwin AJ et al: Ovulation and follicular development
associated with the low-dose oral contraceptive; a randomised controlled
trial. Obstet Gynae 1994 83 1; 29-34.
(8) For information on physiology and NFP, the best single source is
the
website www.woomb.org . Articles such as “Correlating the Signs and
Symptoms of Fertility at the Vulva and Vagina” and “The Continuum” provide
good summaries of decades of collaborative research. There are several
summaries of effectiveness studies on the site.
I have two comments to make with regard to the article about the
rhythm
method. It is not true that the Catholic Church only approves the
“rhythm”
method of family planning. It approves all natural methods and especially
the
Billings Ovulation Method of natural fertility regulation that has a
better than
99% effectiveness rate, as shown in numerous recent published studies.
(www.woomb.org)...
I have two comments to make with regard to the article about the
rhythm
method. It is not true that the Catholic Church only approves the
“rhythm”
method of family planning. It approves all natural methods and especially
the
Billings Ovulation Method of natural fertility regulation that has a
better than
99% effectiveness rate, as shown in numerous recent published studies.
(www.woomb.org)
On a philosophical level L. Bovens’ argument is flawed in trying to
equate
natural miscarriages with induced abortion of a healthy embryo. A ten
year
old child would be able to see the moral distinction between nature taking
its
course as in the case of a miscarriage and deliberately taking action by
swallowing a pill, or other means, to end the life of an embryo.
Everyone makes money or dare I say a profit from "traditional" organ
transplatation through out the world, except the donor. What happened to
supply and demand and free markets? Ultimately it's my body and if I can
help someone prolong their life and not have a high risk to mine and make
something to cover my time and expense..why not?
I'm a healthy mid-40 professional, that does not smoke.
Hey s...
Everyone makes money or dare I say a profit from "traditional" organ
transplatation through out the world, except the donor. What happened to
supply and demand and free markets? Ultimately it's my body and if I can
help someone prolong their life and not have a high risk to mine and make
something to cover my time and expense..why not?
I'm a healthy mid-40 professional, that does not smoke.
Hey sign me up!
Bovens' argument is clever, but it misrepresents Alcorn, and pro-lifers in general, as being concerned about the absolute number of embryonic deaths without distinction as to the cause. But even a cursory reading of Alcorn (e.g.
http://www.epm.org/articles/bcp5400.html) makes it clear that Alcorn's concern is not embr...
Bovens' argument is clever, but it misrepresents Alcorn, and pro-lifers in general, as being concerned about the absolute number of embryonic deaths without distinction as to the cause. But even a cursory reading of Alcorn (e.g.
http://www.epm.org/articles/bcp5400.html) makes it clear that Alcorn's concern is not embryonic death in general, but induced embryonic death: Alcorn merely applies the customary ethical distinction between induced abortion and miscarriage to the situation of a fertilized embryo facing implantation.
Alcorn argues that the use of forms of contraception that create an environment "in utero" inhospitable to implantation (IUD, pill) in so doing induces the death of the embryo (which cannot survive long without implantation), making it ethically comparable to induced abortion. In response, Bovens argues that implantation failures can also conceivably occur when periodic abstinence is being used to avoid pregnancy. However, the convoluted probabilistic arguments Bovens uses to estimate how likely implantation failure might occur, arguments that make up the bulk of the paper, are quite beside the point: regardless of the likelihood of implantation failure under such circumstances, any such failure is spontaneous, not induced, and thus, for Alcorn, is a miscarriage, which he does not consider ethically culpable.
It is only at the very end of his paper that Bovens admits to the possibility that his probabilistic arguments about the likelihood of implantation failure can potentially be addressed by making the distinction between artificially inducing an environment "in utero" inhospitable to implantation, vs. its natural occurrence as part of the ovulatory cycle. But he fails to admit that Alcorn makes this distinction all along; Bovens merely states that he thinks the distinction asks "more from the action/omission doctrine than it can deliver", and leaves it at that. But if Bovens is serious about addressing Alcorn, it is here that his paper should start, not end.
If I understand him correctly he advances three claims. Firstly, he
suggests that the question of consent might not be a relevant
consideration in relation to DNR orders if the treating doctor is able to
“wash his (or her) hands” of a duty of care to the patient. Secondly, he
suggests that in the case of a competent patient the best interests
criterion d...
If I understand him correctly he advances three claims. Firstly, he
suggests that the question of consent might not be a relevant
consideration in relation to DNR orders if the treating doctor is able to
“wash his (or her) hands” of a duty of care to the patient. Secondly, he
suggests that in the case of a competent patient the best interests
criterion does not apply, and that the latter is only applicable once the
patient loses competence. He concludes that my thesis, for it to be
successful, would require me to make three counterintuitive claims.
Namely, that doctors could be; forced to assume a duty of care to a
patient; forced to do a “positive act” to a patient; and required to act
against the doctor’s perceived assessment of the patient’s best interests.
With regard to Mr Foster’s first claim it should be noted that in
most circumstances where a DNR order is written the doctor has already
assumed a duty of care in relation to the patient. The question of whether
resuscitation in the event of cardiopulmonary arrest would be in the
patient’s best interests usually arises in the context of another, often
serious, illness for which that patient is being treated.
Outside of those situations where the patient is already being
treated, a doctor may in fact owe a duty of care to people who are not yet
patients of that doctor. Australian common law holds that a doctor owes a
person a duty of care with whom there exists physical, circumstantial and
causal proximity.[2] That is, the doctor is able logistically to attend a
patient whom that doctor is aware is in need of medical care and to whom
such care would make a medical difference if it were proffered.
In relation to emergency care, Kennedy and Grubb seem to affirm such
a duty
…when a doctor has held himself (sic) out as undertaking to treat
individuals requiring emergency care… by being on duty in an emergency
department of a hospital, he will be deemed to have undertaken to provide
emergency care once he is aware of the need for it.[3]
In response to Mr Foster’s second claim, I would argue that the best
interests criterion is very much applicable in the case of the competent
patient. Lord Templeton said
the doctor… impliedly contracts to act at all times in the best
interests of the patient.[4]
Patients contribute to the doctor’s understanding of what is in their
best interests through discussion of the relevant facts. Patients make
advance assessments of their own future interests when consenting to
surgery and also when making advance directives ruling out certain
treatments should they become incompetent to make medical decisions. In
short, patients can usefully contribute to a decision about whether future
resuscitation might be in their best interests.
Incidentally, the best interests test is not the only consideration
that applies when the patient is no longer competent. The doctor’s
contemporaneous assessment of best interests in an incompetent patient
might be subsumed to the more compelling duties of adhering, as mentioned,
to a valid advance directive [5] (a prior refusal of resuscitation might
constitute such a directive) or complying with the wishes of a valid
surrogate decision maker.
I reject the claims that my thesis means that doctors could be forced
to assume a duty of care and treat patients. They could only be “forced”
to do these things to the extent that the law “requires” them to do
anything. Doctors who choose not to treat would be subject to review and
presumably risk claims of negligence if a duty of care could be proven to
have existed.
Further, as I stated in my paper, no doctor could or ought to be
compelled to act against his or her views of what is in the patient’s best
interests. However, his or her actions, as in any medical case, would be
open to retrospective scrutiny to assess their probity.
Finally, the main purpose of my argument is not to evolve a
persecutory framework compelling doctors to alter their practices but to
ask doctors to think about how patients’ competent wishes contribute to an
assessment of what treatment might or might not be in their best interests
at the end of life. As Mr Foster rightly points out
"If autonomy means anything, it must mean a right to be involved in
decisions about one’s own survival."[1]
What I hope to have persuasively argued in my paper is that a
patient’s competent wishes in this setting ought to be respected.
References
1. Foster CA. Patient consent to DNR orders: some legal observations [electronic response to Biegler P;
Should patient consent be required to write a do not resuscitate order?] jmedethics.com 2003http://jme.bmjjournals.com/cgi/eletters/29/6/359#92
2. Lowns v Woods (1996) Aust Tort Reports 81-376
3. Kennedy I, Grubb A. Medical law: text with materials. London:
Butterworths; 1994: 79
4. Per Lord Templeman in Sidaway v Bethlem Royal Hospital and
Maudsley Hospital Board [1985] 1 All ER 643 HL 665-6
5. Biegler P, Stewart C, Savulescu J, Skene L. Determining the
validity of advance directives. Med J Aust 2000; 172:545-8
Some of my critics draw a distinction between the rhythm method and
natural family planning (NFP). I take the rhythm method to be any method
that relies on abstinence around the time of ovulation. Of course there
are various ways to determine when ovulation occurs, including the
calendar method (Ogino Knauss), examining mucus (Billings) or checking
basal temperature (STM). I do not take this metho...
Some of my critics draw a distinction between the rhythm method and
natural family planning (NFP). I take the rhythm method to be any method
that relies on abstinence around the time of ovulation. Of course there
are various ways to determine when ovulation occurs, including the
calendar method (Ogino Knauss), examining mucus (Billings) or checking
basal temperature (STM). I do not take this method to cover the use of
barrier methods during the fertile period, as some definitions of both
‘NFP’ and ‘the rhythm method’ seem to permit. I find reports on success
rates for this method between 75% as the lowest number for typical use and
99.3% as the highest number for perfect use. Should one use numbers for
perfect use or for typical use in moral arguments? On the one hand, one
could say that a proponent of a method of contraception should not have to
take responsibility for people failing to follow proper instructions. But
on the other hand, recommendations are for real people and real people are
not perfect users. To postulate a 90% success rate does not seem to be
out of line with the available evidence. It is probably somewhat too low
for perfect use and somewhat too high for typical use.
If the method fails, then how does it fail? If the purpose is to
avoid having sex around the time of ovulation, then the following seem to
be reasonable answers. (1) The last time of having sex before the period
of abstinence was too close to ovulation. (2) The first time of having
sex after the period of abstinence was too close to ovulation. (3)
Ovulation was atypically early or late during some cycle and though the
users checked the markers for ovulation, they failed to determine its
occurrence accurately. Or a combination of (1) and (3) or of (1) and (2)
are also reasonable. Since we are talking about typical use, such
failures could be due to self-deception and wishful thinking. (1) raises
the problem of ageing sperm, (2) raises the problem of an ageing ovum and
(3) raises the problem of an atypical cycle.
Now comes the main empirical point of contention. For my argument to
work, it must be the case that the probability of viability given that a
conception occurs with ageing sperm or ovum or during an atypical cycle is
lower than the probability of viability given that a conception occurs
with fresh sperm and a fresh ovum and during a typical cycle. Both Mark
Witty and Anne Williams phrase the objection to this assumption very well.
"There is no evidence that there is any variability of viability of the
conceptus with time of fertilisation within this narrow window," writes
Williams. “Any conception is as viable as the next, barring a fatal
genetic or developmental defect; there is no truth to the 'old sperm' or
'old ovum' speculation...," writes Witty. So let us turn to the relevant
empirical literature.
Tarin et al. (2000) review a fifty-year literature not only on the
effect of ageing gametes on pre-menstruation embryonic loss, but also on
fertilization, spontaneous abortions and the pathology of the offspring.
A range of studies is reviewed of in vivo and in vitro fertilizations with
ageing gametes, involving humans, non-human mammalians, and non-mammalians. These studies are not always univocal. Furthermore, we often
have to extrapolate from non-human animal populations, in vitro contexts,
and patients with a history of infertility to what might be happening in
human populations of normal fertility in in vivo contexts. Sometimes the
best we can do is to guess what would provide the best explanation for
experimental results. Nonetheless, I do think that there is a trend
present which supports the idea that viability given conception may vary
with the age of the ovum, the age of the sperm and whether the cycle is or
is not typical.
As to ageing ova, I quote: "It appears that ... post-ovulatory ageing
of oocytes is associated with: (i) decreased potential of oocytes for
fertilization and pre- and / or post-implantation embryo/fetus development."
(Tarin et al., 2000: 544) Table 1 (Tarin et al., 2000: 533) contains a
range of studies documenting the effect of the ageing of the ovum on
embryo/fetus development and mortality. To pick one example, Wilcox et
al. (1998) study ovulation, hCG levels and intercourse patterns of a
cohort of women attempting pregnancy and find an increase in post-
implantation embryonic loss for intercourse on the day of ovulation in
human populations. Considering the time-lag between intercourse and
fertilisation, these data support the hypothesis that post-ovulatory
ageing of ova compromises embryonic survival. (I should add that Wilcox
et al. (1998) do not record any conceptions from intercourse after the day
of ovulation.) Wilcox et al. (1999) compare late implantations and early
implantations. Late implantations have levels of embryonic loss that are
radically higher (82% after day 11) than early implantations (13% up to
day 9) . However, it is not known what causes these late implantations.
As to old spermatozoa, I quote from Tarin et al., 2000: 544:
"Likewise the ageing of spermatozoa in ... the female reproductive tract ...
is associated with decreased ... potential for fertilization and pre- and/or
post-implantation embryo/fetus development." Table 2 contains entries
with articles documenting the effect of in vivo ageing of spermatozoa in
the female genital tract and increased embryo/fetal mortality with ageing
spermatozoa. Tarin et al. (2000: 542) write: "This notion is supported by
the high mortality rate observed in embryos/fetuses derived from sperm
aged in stagnant environments, e.g in ... the] female reproductive tract."
Parkening and Soderwall, in a study of golden hamsters, write that their
data "indicate that inseminated spermatozoa are capable of penetrating the
zona pellucida and fertilizing some ova after residing 14 to 16 h within
the female reproductive tract, but that the viability of ova fertilized in
this manner is greatly reduced." (1975: 627-8) There are supporting
results about golden hamsters in Bell and Shaver (1982). Vishwanath and
Shannon find that after storage, bull sperm may retain its "oocyte
penetrating ability", yet "mitochondrial DNA damage and chromosomal
abnormalities" could "compromise the viability of the resulting
conceptus." (1997: 321-32)
One might conjecture that if there is a higher rate of early
embryonic loss in conceptions involving ageing gametes, then there would
also be a higher rate of spontaneous abortions. Gray et al. (1995: 1568)
cite a number of studies that confirm this finding. However, in his own
study, he does not find a difference in the spontaneous abortion rate for
conceptions resulting from intercourse on the day before or on the day of
ovulation on the one hand and from intercourse outside this narrow window
on the other hand within the total population. There is however a
significant difference in the spontaneous abortion rate in the
subpopulation of women who have had spontaneous abortions before. There
is no conclusive interpretation of these results.
Let us now turn to atypical cycles. There are many open questions
here and much of my evidence comes from consulting with researchers in the
field. Implantation rates are dependent on the nature of the embryo and
the development of the endometrium. In IVF (in vitro fertilisation),
ovulation is timed carefully by adjusting drug dosages so that it comes
neither too early nor too late. This might indicate that the quality of
the ovum could be a function of ovulation time and since we can control
for fertilisation in IVF, the concern is a concern about the viability of
the embryo. In IUI (in utero insemination), some doctors will refrain
from inseminating in case of an early ovulation. This might indicate that
the quality of the ovum is compromised when there is early ovulation or
that a short follicular phase may compromise the development of the
endometrium. Early ovulation is believed to correlate with higher rates
of oocyte aneuploidy leading to more pre- and post-implantation embryonic
loss due to chromosal abnormalities. About late ovulations, Tarin et al.
(2000: 535) write that "...under particular circumstances, including long
follicular phases ... fully grown GV oocytes may undergo pre-ovulatory
ageing before the occurrence of the endogenous LH surge ..." (2000: 535) He
also presents a list of studies documenting the effect of pre-ovulatory
ageing on fertilization, the development of the embryo and the offspring.
(2000: 534)
Whitty objects to my use of the figure of 50% of embryonic loss,
claims that such high figures are based on old and questionable studies
(from 1956 and 1975), and that animal studies give single-digit
percentages. A standard source for embryonic mortality is Edmonds (1982).
Edmonds assesses embryonic loss by the appearance and disappearance of hCG
in the urine at the time of implantation and presents a figure of 62%.
This underestimates the actual percentage since it does not count pre-implantation loss. In Wilcox et al.'s study (1999) the pre-menstruation
embryonic loss plus miscarriages is at 33%. Why is there this
discrepancy? The only explanation that I can see is that Edmonds samples
from a normal population, whereas Wilcox restricts his population to
couples without previous fertility problems. In any case, considering
that this does not measure pre-implantation loss, a figure of 50% for
normal populations does not seem outlandish in the face of these data.
So far I have tried to defend the assumptions that come into the
model. But of course, it is another thing to check whether the
predictions of the model hold true in the real world. Clearly we know too
little to fill in the values of all the parameters. It may be the case
that, say, the viability given conception is variable, but this
variability is not sufficiently great to obtain meaningful differences
between embryonic death rates for condom users and NFP users. Or there
can be hidden variables that are not included in the model. In principle,
it is possible to do the following empirical test. One could compare post
-implantation embryonic loss rates between condom users and NFP users by
checking for hCG in urine tests. However, in practice, this would require
quite a large number of subjects, because in any given cycle, there would
only be a relatively small number of conceptions. This would be one step
forward, but it would still not yield information about pre-implantation
embryonic loss, because hCG does not register in the woman’s blood or
urine before implantation.
Let us turn to the philosophical objections. My critics claim that
even if I were right about the empirical data, there would still be a
moral divide between NFP and contraceptive pills, because the embryonic
deaths occurring on NFP would be "natural deaths" whereas the deaths
occurring on contraceptive pills would be "induced deaths", in Ira
Winter’s words. Justin and Sue Fryer talk about "letting nature take its
way" versus "deliberately taking action by swallowing a pill, or other
means, to end the life of an embryo". And Mark Whitty points to the
relevance of the doctrine of double effect.
These are difficult issues that require a much more careful analysis
than what I can offer at this point. Let us clearly bracket the empirical
issues from the philosophical issues. My critics say that even if I were
right about the empirical details, then we could still invoke the
action/omission doctrine or the doctrine of double effect to draw a
distinction between NFP and contraceptive pills. So let us not quibble
about empirical data from here on and suppose—to make things simple—that a
particular implementation of NFP and a particular contraceptive pill,
would lead to the same number n of conceptions, lead to the same number of
embryonic deaths d, and lead to the same number of live births m. And let
us suppose that condoms lead to the same number m of live births but with
fewer conceptions and hence fewer embryonic deaths. A final alternative
is abstinence with carefully targeted pregnancies, leading to m life
births with even fewer conceptions and even fewer embryonic deaths.
Let us do the following admittedly fanciful thought experiment.
Suppose that conceptions always lead to live births. However, all these
contraceptive techniques would have the same mechanisms and consequences
as they now have, substituting neonatal death for embryonic death. So a
contraceptive pill user would have n conceptions, n live births, but d
deaths of newborns and hence only m children that survive for longer than,
say, one week. Similarly for NFP, condom usage and abstinence with
targeted pregnancies. Would there not be an outcry about any method that
would have an excessive neonatal death rate? Could we defend NFP on
grounds that the deaths of these newborns is just nature’s way or on
grounds that these deaths are not intended? I don’t think so. If embryos
have the same moral status as newborns, then why would we think that we
can put up such defences for NFP involving embryonic death?
Now I am a friend of the action/omission doctrine and the doctrine of
double effect. For example, as to the action/omission doctrine, I do
agree that one has to have better reasons—i.e. the prognosis has to be
worse—before one is justified to withdraw treatment (action) rather than
withhold treatment (omission). As to the doctrine of double effect,
suppose that I can advance the war effort to the same extent by target
bombing, say, by bombing a depot, while expecting to kill n innocent
civilians living around the depot as collateral damage, as by terror
bombing, say, by bombing a neighbourhood with the intention of killing n
innocent civilians. I do agree that terror bombing is worse than target
bombing. But just to say that bad effects did not come about due to
direct agency or were not intended is not sufficient to make a practice
permissible on the action/omission doctrine or on the doctrine of double
effect. The bad effects also have to be outweighed by the good effects
and furthermore, there must be no other practice (in which the bad effects
do not come about due to direct agency or were not intended) that achieves
the same good effects while incurring fewer bad effects.
Further to the action/omission doctrine: There is a continuum between
agency (say, a direct killing of an embryo) and an omission (say, not
providing a drug that would prevent a miscarriage). Now one might argue
that, on this continuum, "taking a pill so that fertilisation is unlikely
to occur or so that the endometrium is inhospitable for incoming embryos"
is more on the action side than "organizing your sex life so that
fertilisation is unlikely to occur or so that embryos are either non-viable or come in at times when the endometrium is not hospitable". But
is the distance on this continuum sufficiently great to make the former
qualify as a grave sin and the latter as a morally permissible method of
birth control? I am not convinced. Maybe it is worse to remove edible
plants and animals from an island to make it inhospitable and then to drop
off someone on it than to carefully pick a time of the year to drop off
someone when you know the island not to be hospitable for human
habitation. But really, is it that much worse? And furthermore, even if,
given our assumptions about the numbers, contraceptive pills are worse
than NFP on action/omission grounds, then would one not want to reverse
this judgment if embryonic death rates for NFP would come to exceed
embryonic death rates for contraceptive pills to a sufficient degree?
Clearly we carry some responsibility for the consequences of our
omissions. If embryonic deaths are a bad thing, then should we not try to
minimize them? Indeed, we should take due care, also in our omissions.
And, given my assumptions, there are alternatives available, viz. condoms
and abstinence with targeted conceptions, that come at a lower embryonic
death rate.
I have two concerns with invoking the doctrine of double effect.
Clearly it is not enough to say that an NFP user does not intend the
embryonic death. This would get a pill user off the hook. She could just
say that she only intends to block ovulation by taking this pill and
furthermore she intends this as a means not to become pregnant. A
proponent of the doctrine of double effect would just say to the pill user
that if embryonic death were not to occur she would shoot short of her
target – there would simply be more pregnancies. Embryonic death is
integral to reaching her goal while, say, the deaths of innocent civilians
in target bombing are not. But the same response holds for the NFP users.
Without the embryonic deaths, there would be more pregnancies.
Secondly, target bombing would be no longer permissible if there were
another way to gain the same military advantages at a lower cost in the
lives of innocent civilians. But is this not what we are facing in the
case of NFP? There are alternative ways to gain the same advantages at a
lower cost of embryonic deaths, e.g. by condom use. Now I realize that
there may be independent grounds for opposing condom use as a malum in se,
but then there is the possibility of abstinence with targeted conceptions.
Granted, the gains of sex are lost in abstinence, but do they weigh up
against embryonic deaths?
Clearly there are many open questions in this area. And I have not
even touched on questions about the status of the embryo. These are not
only questions in the context of the pro-life versus pro-choice debate.
For instance, some critics have pointed out that many of my embryonic
deaths are deaths of defective embryos and defective embryos are not
possible persons. Other critics have claimed that embryonic deaths as
such are not a bad thing, but that killing an embryo is nonetheless a
wrong action. Many such questions remain unexplored.
My intention here was to point out that an appeal to the
action/omission doctrine or the doctrine of double effect does not
straightforwardly block the argument. Maybe it can be blocked. To make
headway on this issue will require some serious thinking and constructive
dialogue.
Let me take this occasion to thank my critics in JME, e-mail
correspondents and bloggers for their thoughtful comments. I am also
grateful for helpful (e-)conversations with Roger Gosden, Kathy Hoeger,
Kathy King, Michael Otsuka, Alexander Pruss, Danny Schust, Alan Thornhill,
and Alex Voorhoeve.
References
Bell, C.L. and Shaver E.L. (1982) Analysis of preimplantation golden
hamster conceptuses resulting from spermatozoa aged in utero. Gamete Res.,
6: 199-207.
Edmonds, D.K., Lindsay, K.S., Miller, J.F. Williamson, E. and Wood,
P.J. (1982) Early embryonic mortality in women. Fertil. Steril., 38, 447-
53.
Gray, R.H., Simpson, J.L., Kambic, R.T., Queenan, J.T., Mena, P.,
Perez, A. and Barbato, M. (1995) Timing of conception and the risk of
spontaneous abortions occurring during the use of natural family planning.
Am. J. Obstet. Gynecol., 172, 1567-72.
Parkening, T.A. and Soderwall, A.L. (1975) Delayed fertilization and
preimplantation loss in senescent golden hamsters. Biol. Reprod., 12, 618-
31.
Tarin, J.J., Perez-Albala, S. and Cano, A. (2000) Consequences on
offspring of abnormal function in ageing gametes. Hum. Reprod. Update, 6,
532-49.
Vishwanath, R. and Shannon, P. (1997) Do sperm cells age? A review of
the physiological changes in sperm during storage at ambient temperature.
Reproduction, Fertility and Development, 9, 321-32.
Wilcox, A.J., Weinberg, C.R. and Baird, D.D. (1998) Post-ovulatory
ageing of the human oocyte and embryo failure. Human. Reprod., 13, 394-7.
Wilcox, A.J., Baird, D.D. and Weinberg C.R. (1999) Time of
implantation of the conceptus and loss of pregnancy. N. Engl. J. Med.,
340, 1796-99.
Bennett Foddy interprets the view I express in 'Deafness, culture,
and choice' (JME 2002: 28) correctly: deaf children are contingently, and
not necessarily, worse off as a result of their disability. Indeed, this
claims seems almost tautological: to be better or worse off is inherently
relational, so it is easy to imagine worlds in which the deaf would not be
worse off. A world in which everyone was de...
Bennett Foddy interprets the view I express in 'Deafness, culture,
and choice' (JME 2002: 28) correctly: deaf children are contingently, and
not necessarily, worse off as a result of their disability. Indeed, this
claims seems almost tautological: to be better or worse off is inherently
relational, so it is easy to imagine worlds in which the deaf would not be
worse off. A world in which everyone was deaf is one obvious case.
But Foddy's claim that this fact shows the deaf have a right to
ensure that their children are also deaf is false. His argument seems to
have two premises. First, he argues that if the deaf are only contingently
worse off than the hearing, then this must be because they are
discriminated against. "[T]heir deafness is a constraint only because our
society discriminates against those who cannot hear", he writes. Second,
he implies that since their lives are constrained only as a result of
discrimination, we have no right to object to their parents' choices to
ensure that they are deaf. Both claims are false.
First, it is false to think that in all cases in which X is worse off
as a result of Y's actions, X has had her rights violated by Y. Y might
have been justified in acting as she did, even in cases in which X is an
innocent bystander. Every person has different abilities and limitations,
but our social world is necessarily designed so that certain abilities are
rewarded more than others and certain limitations are more constraining.
This is simply a result of the fact that choices must be made: buildings
must be designed, systems of communication chosen, modes of transport
developed, and so on. Some people are worse off as a consequence of these
choices, through no fault of their own. This is simply inevitable.
This kind of situation prevails with regard to the deaf. Moreover,
our choices here are not arbitrary, but instead reflect the advantages of
using using all the modes of communication available to us. Foddy thinks
that the only good argument which might be advanced for the universal
abandonment of sound as a means of communication and entertainment would
turn on the transition costs of moving to a soundless society, but this is
false. Sound has qualities which vision does not. It is not limited by the
direction of the gaze of individuals, it is able to wake sleeping people
(think of the difficulty of replacing fire alarms with lights which would
be as effective), and so on. In choosing a world in which sound is
important, we make a justified choice. As a result, the deaf are worse
off. But they are not discriminated against, because their rights are not
infringed (which isn't to say that the deaf are not discriminated against
in many other ways, of course).
So Foddy's first premise is straightforwardly false. His second
premise is also disputable, if not as obviously wrong as the first.
Suppose the disadvantages of the deaf were entirely a product of
discrimination. Would it not still be the case that the choice of deaf
parents to ensure that their children would be worse off than they would
otherwise be is, at least, questionable? Of course, all of us, who (in
this scenario) are responsible for the discrimination against the deaf
would bear a significant portion of the blame for the disadvantages of
such deaf children. But this would not exonerate the deaf parent entirely.
Suppose you knew that a crazed gunman would shoot indiscriminately at
every person he saw in the park today. If you nevertheless took your child
to the park, we would think much less of you, despite the fact that the
risks faced by your child were produced by the evil actions of the gunman.
The fact that a harm is a product of wrongful actions does not give a
parent the right to place their child in its way.
The desire of deaf parents to have children who resemble them and who
identify with their culture is understandable. Nevertheless, there are
powerful reasons to think that, all things considered, this is a desire
upon which they ought not to act.
Dear Editor
Dr. Biegler concludes that patient consent to a DNR order should be required [1]. He rightly locates the reason for that ethical demand in the principle of autonomy. If autonomy means anything, it must mean a right to be involved in decisions about one’s own survival. It is also correct to say that the law of consent, at least in common law jurisdictions, is built on the philosophical foundation of au...
Dear Editor,
Whilst I am an advocate for dialogue and mutual understanding and indeed have written on the possible acceptance of emergency contraception in instances of rape, I find this article by L. Bovens rather disturbing and at most insulting to the general Catholic population. Although he uses the term pro-life, this can only be an emotive attempt, rather than rational argumentation, since 'pro-lifers' have b...
Dear Editor
Erin and Harris [1] suggest that we need a regulated market in live donor organs to make good the shortfall in organs available for transplantation. However, the example of the third world shows that to sell a kidney is virtually always an act of desperation when other options for raising money are exhausted, for example Goyal et al.[2] reported that 96% of participants in their survey of kidney...
Dear Editor,
This article on Reproductive Ethics is unfortunate in a number of respects, and while I would not identify with the pro-life movement of the article, I feel it necessary to respond from the standpoint of a proponent of the modern Billings Ovulation Method of Natural Family Planning (NFP).
NFP Methods
Bovens seems to choose to reduce all NFP to one approach, the defi...
Dear Editor,
I have two comments to make with regard to the article about the rhythm method. It is not true that the Catholic Church only approves the “rhythm” method of family planning. It approves all natural methods and especially the Billings Ovulation Method of natural fertility regulation that has a better than 99% effectiveness rate, as shown in numerous recent published studies. (www.woomb.org)...
Dear Editor
Everyone makes money or dare I say a profit from "traditional" organ transplatation through out the world, except the donor. What happened to supply and demand and free markets? Ultimately it's my body and if I can help someone prolong their life and not have a high risk to mine and make something to cover my time and expense..why not?
I'm a healthy mid-40 professional, that does not smoke. Hey s...
Dear Editor,
Bovens' argument is clever, but it misrepresents Alcorn, and pro-lifers in general, as being concerned about the absolute number of embryonic deaths without distinction as to the cause. But even a cursory reading of Alcorn (e.g. http://www.epm.org/articles/bcp5400.html) makes it clear that Alcorn's concern is not embr...
Dear Editor
I thank Mr Foster for his response.[1]
If I understand him correctly he advances three claims. Firstly, he suggests that the question of consent might not be a relevant consideration in relation to DNR orders if the treating doctor is able to “wash his (or her) hands” of a duty of care to the patient. Secondly, he suggests that in the case of a competent patient the best interests criterion d...
Dear Editor,
Some of my critics draw a distinction between the rhythm method and natural family planning (NFP). I take the rhythm method to be any method that relies on abstinence around the time of ovulation. Of course there are various ways to determine when ovulation occurs, including the calendar method (Ogino Knauss), examining mucus (Billings) or checking basal temperature (STM). I do not take this metho...
Dear Editor
Bennett Foddy interprets the view I express in 'Deafness, culture, and choice' (JME 2002: 28) correctly: deaf children are contingently, and not necessarily, worse off as a result of their disability. Indeed, this claims seems almost tautological: to be better or worse off is inherently relational, so it is easy to imagine worlds in which the deaf would not be worse off. A world in which everyone was de...
Pages