Dr. Miller cites the "professional integrity of physicians" and the
uncertainty of whether additional interventions will restore a patient's
desire to live.
Does Dr. Miller's professional integrity include honesty,
truthfulness, and sincerity when speaking to severely treatment-resistant
patients? Particularly with respect to the efficacy of treatments that
will provide rapid response and prolonged remission? D...
Dr. Miller cites the "professional integrity of physicians" and the
uncertainty of whether additional interventions will restore a patient's
desire to live.
Does Dr. Miller's professional integrity include honesty,
truthfulness, and sincerity when speaking to severely treatment-resistant
patients? Particularly with respect to the efficacy of treatments that
will provide rapid response and prolonged remission? Does that integrity
extend to honestly communicating with these patients regarding scientific
data on the likelihood, severity, and duration of relapse or recurrence?
Or is Dr. Miller referring to the integrity that embodies a
physician's personal ethics, morality and righteousness? Given Dr.
Miller's emphasis of the uncertainty about whether additional
interventions with the patient can improve quality of life, it appears the
physician's beliefs should trump the ability of informed patients to
decide.
As Drs. Schuklenk and van de Vathorst stated, "if the pace of
developments leading to therapeutic success in major depressive disorder
is anything to go by, many
people suffering from TRD would have reason to be sceptical about the odds
of such a treatment regimen coming about within a timeframe that they
would consider acceptable."
Patients suffering from treatment-resistant major depression have
likely undergone extensive long-term professional psychiatric care.
"Typically they would have tried a fairly significant number of
antidepressants, psychotherapy, probably
electroconvulsive therapy, and they would have experienced the failure of
these varied therapeutic approaches."
Dr. Miller places considerable weight on the "uncertainty of whether
additional interventions will restore a patient's desire to live." As Dr.
Schuklenk points out, this argument unjustly ignores "the high burden that
is paid by patients who happen to wait unsuccessfully for a successful
treatment that may not come about at all or that may come about too late."
Drs. Schuklenk and van de Vathorst provided sound recommendations in
their article. Dr. Miller appears to personally disagree.
Bentham's hedonic, or felicific, calculus doesn't work, in practice,
either, so the criticism of a calculus being difficult or not absolute
applies equally to utilitarianism.
The hedonic calculus allows conclusions with no benefit, or negative
benefit, or positive pain for some. If the net calculation is positive for
all, then the negative consequences for one or more individuals is
subsumed by the greater good...
Bentham's hedonic, or felicific, calculus doesn't work, in practice,
either, so the criticism of a calculus being difficult or not absolute
applies equally to utilitarianism.
The hedonic calculus allows conclusions with no benefit, or negative
benefit, or positive pain for some. If the net calculation is positive for
all, then the negative consequences for one or more individuals is
subsumed by the greater good and, essentially, ignored. Worse, you can, in
theory, have a negative consequence for one individual, such as torture,
that seems acceptable because of the overall positive result.
With transactional audit, every individual has an absolute
requirement for some quantum of dignity.
If the dignity of any one person is to be compromised, to maximise
dignity, that is explicit in the calculation.
A decision to act against the dignity of one or more, is then the
least bad option - rather than, with utilitarianism, an the optimal
decision.
I think this is an important step forwards, ethically. As the article
puts it: 'The starting point is that everyone's dignity counts. Everyone
is a stakeholder in every transaction.'. Even after the decision, the
importance of individual dignity remains.
Wouldn't next step be, similar to law, to try to establish
precedents? To invite the registration of specific decisions that used
transactional analysis, so that they can be referred to, eventually, as a
body of knowledge, a guide for future decisions?
Abstract worked examples, or even concrete examples worked by one
person, are less likely to be complete, satisfactory, and widely
considerate of all stakeholders, and their dignity, than a recorded
history of decisions made in similar circumstances, and building on
precedent.
Having a collection of such decisions as a benchmark would also make
matters much easier, and, one hopes, fairer, when the time available
decide is too short to carry out a full audit.
The only specific problem I see, with the maximisation of dignity as
an objective, is much the same as for utilitarianism. If 100 stakeholders
are distant enough for their dignity to be impacted by 1/100th, then they
have the equivalent stake in dignity as the patient. Fair enough, but, if
you consider 20 million people, they only need a very tiny stake indeed to
counter the interests of the patient.
This seems wrong. Some cut-off distance, for stakeholders not in
close proximity to the patient, seems necessary to mitigate the potential
tyranny of the majority.
In their
recent article Farrell and Brazier [1]
assert that the recent decision in Montgomery v Lanarkshire
Health Board [2]
should not cause doctors any anxiety or concern. However the legal perspective
on the case is perhaps not the same as the clinician's perspective. From the
clinician's perspective there are reasonable concerns.
Firstly, we
should note that the damages in Montgomery amounted to approximately
5.25 million pounds [3]
and were recovered in negligence as a result of the breach of the duty to
adequately inform. An action for a breach of the GMC rules of conduct would not
have resulted in an award of this size. Montgomery may not have changed
the expected rules of conduct for clinicians, but in terms of enlarging the
extent of liability for breach, the case has taken the velvet glove off the
mailed fist.
Secondly,
the model underlying medical decision-making is now to firmly place the
liability for ordinary consequences flowing from medical decision-making in the
hands of the patient:
"treats [patients], so far as possible, as
adults who are capable of understanding that medical treatment is uncertain of
success and may involve risks, accepting responsibility for the taking of risks
affecting their own lives, and living with the consequences of their
choices."[4]
The
obligation on the doctor is, through the provision of information, to place the
patient in the position to make the necessary choices. In order to achieve this
outcome it is asserted that the Court has made a combination move in Montgomery:
(a) there is a shift in the yardstick used to
judge the standard of disclosure from the Bolam
standard towards a modified objective patient standard; and
(b) there a shift of view point from the
perspective of the clinician towards the perspective of the patient.
The first
point has been well telegraphed by the Courts as Farrell and Brazier point out.
However, the second point is not so clearly already embedded in clinical
practice. Briefly, let us put aside the reasonable patient disclosure limb of
the standard and focus only upon the particular patient disclosure limb of the
test.[5] The particular patient disclosure limb
disclosure requires disclosure where:
(i)
the doctor is aware that the particular patient would be likely to attach
significance to the risk; or
(ii) the doctor should
reasonably be aware that the particular patient would be likely to attach
significance to the risk.
The
question has changed from, what can and should the clinician deliver to what
does this patient need to know? [6]
"The assessment is therefore
fact-sensitive, and sensitive also to the characteristics of the patient."[7]
Conforming
to such a particularist legal rule is hard in
practice because it requires the clinician to have some insight into the thoughts
of each patient. Thoughts that the patient need not express until the court
hearing for breach of the duty of care, as the facts of Montgomery
demonstrate.
Given that
the mind of the patient is not necessarily in full purview to the clinician the
question is what does the clinician have to do in practice in the particular
case in order to prove valid consent? Simply answering the patient's questions
is no longer enough. A signed consent form is no longer enough. What would be
enough?
Developing
and then embedding a process approach to consent with adequate documentation to
avoid liability is a new demand on already overstretched resources. The Court
recognized that more clinical time will be needed in order to secure adequate
consent.[8]
But this will have to be costed and delivered.
The
decision in Montgomery leaves process failures to be challenged in
public law rather than in tort.[9]
Given the differences between judicial review actions and negligence actions,
the effect is likely to be to push liability for process failures downstream
onto clinicians.
Thirdly,
there is the question of whether a patient can be told too much? After the
fact, the patient can complain that there was something could have been known
and that were not told that adversely affected their judgement sufficiently to
justify an action in negligence. But, by analogy, can the patient also complain
about facts that they were told but should not have been told? Would such a
positive affront to the autonomy of the patient be actionable?
In
conclusion, there are things in the judgement that reasonably give clinicians
pause for thought.
[1] Farrell AM, Brazier M. Not so new
directions in the law of consent? Examining Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health
Board. J Med Ethics 2015 (online first) doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102861
[2]Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health
Board[2015] UKSC 11
[4]Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health
Board[2015] UKSC 11 at para 81.
[5]Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board[2015]
UKSC 11 at para 87.
[6] Heywood R. R.I.P. Sidaway:
patient-oriented disclosure-a standard worth waiting for? Montgomery v
Lanarkshire Health Board[2015] UKSC 11. Med Law Rev 2015;23(3):455-66.
[7]Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health
Board[2015] UKSC 11 at para 89.
[8]Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board[2015]
UKSC 11 at para 93.
[9]Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board[2015]
UKSC 11 at para 75.
Despite a damning 2014 Australian Human Rights Commission report into
the plight of children in immigration detention, the disturbing findings
of reported in the 2015 Moss Inquiry into allegations relating to
conditions and circumstances at the Australian regional migrant processing
centre in Nauru, and compelling evidence of the harm suffered by these
children, Australia continues to hold children in im...
Despite a damning 2014 Australian Human Rights Commission report into
the plight of children in immigration detention, the disturbing findings
of reported in the 2015 Moss Inquiry into allegations relating to
conditions and circumstances at the Australian regional migrant processing
centre in Nauru, and compelling evidence of the harm suffered by these
children, Australia continues to hold children in immigrant detention.
Procedural justice has been retarded or withheld, and for a country rich
in resources and previously generous in providing opportunities for
migrants, distributive justice has been tragically lacking. Recently
enacted border protection legislation constrains government contracted
staff from disclosing the circumstances in immigration detention centres.
The Australian Federal Government has repeatedly, and arrogantly, flouted
its obligations under International Human Rights Legislation and
Conventions with bipartisan political support. International action is
warranted with Australia's bid for a seat on the United Nations Human
Rights Council providing a potential lever for catalysing change. It would
be unconscionable for Australia to take a seat on the Council while
refugee children remain in detention.
In 2014 the Australian Human Rights Commission published a damning
report, "The forgotten children: national inquiry into children in
immigration detention", which found that mandatory immigration detention
was harmful to children and violated the Convention on the Rights of the
Child.1 Despite this unequivocal moral and legal condemnation, 174
children remain in immigration detention facilities as of 30 November
2014.2
David Isaacs' eloquent discussion of the conundrum facing health care
professionals working in Australia's immigration detention centres focuses
on the competing moral duties to provide care, thus effectively condoning
torture, and/or to speak out, with likely legal reprisal.3 However,
holding children, often for extended periods, in detention presents an
untenable ethical situation. Perpetuating this practice, despite
confirmation of abuse, and expert evidence of long term - avoidable -
medical and psychology harm, provides incontrovertible evidence that the
Australian government has been derelict in balancing the principles of
beneficence (doing good) and non-maleficence (avoiding or minimizing harm)
when dealing with these children.4-8
Procedural justice has been retarded or withheld, with inordinately
long periods of detention and no indication of the period of confinement.
Australia, a country that is rich in resources and previously demonstrated
laudable generosity in providing opportunities for migrants, could rightly
be accused of withholding distributive justice from these children.
Human rights legislation can be a useful foil against political
expediency. It can buffer prejudicial actions against minorities where
these measures are popular with the powerful majority.9 Tragically, as
demonstrated by the arrogant response of Australia's former prime
minister, quoted by Isaacs, compliance by a country's government with its
humanitarian obligations requires a willingness to acknowledge fault where
this exists and to take decisive corrective action.
The freedom of those Australians most acutely confronted with the
realities of life in detention facilities to voice their concern without
fear of retribution may have been legally muzzled in Australia. Bipartisan
flouting of international legal obligations has not provoked the ire of
the broader populace beyond some enlightened non-governmental
organisations and professional medical and ethics bodies. Thus,
international action is warranted. Australia's bid for one of the two
seats on the United Nations Human Rights Council that will become vacant
for the period 2018 to 2020 should be used as a catalyst to accelerate
reforms to Australia's offshore processing arrangements, particular those
relating to imprisoning children. It would be unconscionable for Australia
to take a seat on the UN Human Rights Council while refugee children
remain in detention. International pressure appears morally justified in
the cause of justice.
References
1. The Forgotten Children: National Inquiry into Children in
Immigration Detention. Australian Human Rights Commission, 2014.
https://www.humanrights.gov.au/sites/default/files/document/publication/forgotten_children_2014.pdf
(accessed 29 Dec 2015).
2. Australian Government Department of Immigration and Border
Protection. Immigration detention community statistics summary. 30
November 2015. https://www.border.gov.au/about/reports-
publications/research-statistics/statistics/live-in-australia/immigration-
detention (accessed 29 Dec 2015).
3. Isaacs D. Are healthcare professionals working in Australia's
immigration detention centres condoning torture? J Med Ethics Published
Online First: 23 December 2015.
4. Murphy L. Beneficence, law and liberty; the case of required
rescue. Georgetown Law J 2001; 3: 605-65.
5. Dudley M, Steel Z, Mares S, et al. Children and young people in
immigration detention. Curr Opin Psychiatry 2012; 25: 285-92.
6. Green JP, Eagar K. The health of people in Australian immigration
detention centres. Med J Aust 2010; 192: 65-70
7. Moss P. Review into recent allegations relating to conditions and
circumstances at the Regional Processing Centre in Nauru, 6 February 2015.
https://www.border.gov.au/ReportsandPublications/Documents/reviews-and-
inquiries/review-conditions-circumstances-nauru.pdf (accessed 29 Dec
2015).
8. Paxton G, Tosif S, Graham H, et al.
Perspective: The forgotten children: National inquiry into children in
immigration detention. J Paediatr Child Hlth 2015; 51: 365-8.
9. McNeill PM. Public health ethics: asylum seekers and the case for
political action. Bioethics 2003: 17: 487-502.
Is prostitution harmful? And if it is harmful, should it be illegal
to buy (or sell) sexual services? And if so, should there ever be any
exceptions? What about for people with certain disabilities--say--who
might find it difficult or even impossible to find a sexual partner if
they weren't allowed to exchange money for sex? Do people have a "right"
to s...
Is prostitution harmful? And if it is harmful, should it be illegal
to buy (or sell) sexual services? And if so, should there ever be any
exceptions? What about for people with certain disabilities--say--who
might find it difficult or even impossible to find a sexual partner if
they weren't allowed to exchange money for sex? Do people have a "right"
to sexual fulfillment?
In a recent issue of the Journal of Medical Ethics, Frej Klem
Thomsen[1] explores these and other controversial questions. His focus is
on the issue of exceptions--specifically for those with certain
disabilities. According to Thomsen, a person is "relevantly disabled" (for
the sake of this discussion) if and only if:
(1) she has sexual needs, and desires to exercise her sexuality, and
(2) she has an anomalous physical or mental condition that, given her
social circumstances, sufficiently limits her possibilities of exercising
her sexuality, including fulfilling her sexual needs. (p. 455)
There is a lot to say here. First, in order to figure out the merits
of making an exception to a general ban on prostitution (for people with
disabilities or for anyone else), we have to start by deciding what to
think about the advisability of such a ban in the first place. For, if we
don't think that it's a good idea to begin with, then we can skip all the
talk about making exemptions, and just argue against the overall ban.
But Thomsen doesn't pursue that route. Instead, he wants to make a case
for an exception. So, he has to try to convince his reader that a general
prohibition makes at least some kind of moral and/or practical sense. How
does he go about making this argument?
A case for prohibition?
Thomsen spells it out like this:
(1) Prostitution is bad because it causes harm to prostitutes.
(2) We have reason to avoid harm to persons.
(3) Prohibiting prostitution will reduce harm to prostitutes.
(4) Therefore, we have reason to prohibit prostitution. (p. 453)
Is this a good argument in favor of prohibition?
The harm of prostitution
We can start with the first claim: that prostitution is bad because
it causes harm to prostitutes. Is that a convincing claim?
It does have a certain intuitive appeal, and most people would
probably say "yes." But in another recent essay (also published in the
JME), the philosopher Ole Martin Moen has put forward a powerful set of
arguments that call into question conventional wisdom.[2]
According to Moen, while it is true that prostitution is not a
harmless line of work:
(1) it is no more inherently harmful (on balance) than a long list of
other occupations which we do not see fit to ban, but instead choose to
regulate; and
(2) most of the harm that does go along with prostitution is actually
a consequence of its being illegal (and otherwise socially stigmatized)--
i.e., contingent, external factors that have little to do with
prostitution per se.
Let us take a closer look at Moen's argument. To do this, we can
start by considering one specific type of harm as an example: the
apparently higher rates of physical and mental health problems among sex
workers compared to members of the general population.
As Moen argues, this purported harm of prostitution might be due--at least
in part--to the legal prohibition against the activity, which prevents sex
workers from taking certain actions that would predictably improve their
lot. For example: "joining labour unions, organizing their work in
brothels, renting a place where they can work, hiring security agencies,
advertising and forming work contracts (regarding salary, working hours,
working conditions, health insurance, retirement savings, and so on)"
([2], p. 3).
In fact, Moen does a good job of addressing most of the arguments
that claim to show that prostitution is inherently harmful (including in
ways that are not just physical, but also more abstract, symbolic, or
moral), by performing a similar analysis for each one. Readers who are
skeptical, of course, can read Moen's paper themselves, and reach their
own conclusions.
Thomsen's critique
Thomsen actually considers Moen's argument. Only he doesn't find it
entirely convincing. Among other issues, his main objection that even if
"extrinsic" factors like social stigma and legal prohibition were
responsible for some of the harms associated with prostitution, they
wouldn't necessarily account for all of the harms associated with
prostitution. (As far as I can tell, Moen doesn't dispute this claim, but
let us set that aside for now.)
To support his position, Thomsen cites an empirical study by a
researcher named Vanwesenbeeck.[3] According to Thomsen, this study showed
that "roughly half--but no more than half--[of] the variance in [certain
negative emotional outcomes] experienced by indoor prostitutes in the
Netherlands was explained by external factors including stigma, lack of
control and poor working conditions" ([1], p. 453, emphasis added).
The implication, then, is that the other half of these negative
outcomes (for example, emotional exhaustion) must be due to something
intrinsic to prostitution.
Intrinsic vs. extrinsic
There are a few ways to respond to this line of thought. First, there
is the problem of non-random sampling: some people turn to prostitution
because of pre-existing issues with addiction or mental health, and so the
arrow of causation is not entirely clear. Second, it seems unlikely that
the study by Vanwesenbeeck measured every possible "external factor" that
could be responsible for the various harms of prostitution, which
introduces a further limitation to what we can infer from these results.
But even if it did--so, even if we were justified in saying that "roughly
half" of the variance in (say) emotional exhaustion experienced by this
particular sample of Dutch prostitutes was due to something intrinsic
about their selling sex--we would still have to put this information in
context.
What sort of context do I mean? Well, consider the fact that many
careers contribute to, e.g., emotional exhaustion (and other negative
emotional outcomes): just think of the burn-out that grief and trauma
counselors experience, for example, which is probably due to factors that
are (at least in large part) intrinsic to that particular line of work. Or
think of the various harms that are "built in" to any number of jobs, like
the dangers of construction work, or professional boxing; or the job-
insecurity of being an actor (unemployed after every show); or the
"degrading" nature of, say, collecting people's garbage or cleaning out
their toilets.
When it comes to these careers, however, no one thinks we should
prohibit people from choosing to pursue them, just on account of the fact
that they carry some degree of risk, or are stigmatized, or are otherwise
less than ideal. Instead, we try to think of ways of reducing the various
risks that are involved, and/or we compensate people--usually monetarily--
for the harms and difficulties that do in fact come along with their
choice of employment.
None of this is to suggest that the intrinsic harms of prostitution
are identical to those in the other lines of work just mentioned. They may
very well be much more problematic. The point is only that the mere fact
that some occupation has intrinsic harms, whatever those turn out to be,
is not sufficient to show (without further argument) that it should
therefore be prohibited.
The importance of choice
Note the importance of choice here. My position has to do with people
--men, women, intersex, and transgender people--who freely choose to sell
sexual services in exchange for money. If someone is forced to sell sexual
services, that is sexual slavery, not prostitution, and that is a
different matter entirely.[4]
Now, someone might argue that prostitution is so inherently harmful
or degrading, that someone would only "choose" to exchange sex for money
if in reality they were forced by their circumstances (i.e., extreme
poverty).[4] A similar argument has been made about the prospect of
establishing a market for selling kidneys: only people who are pressured
(by their circumstances) to sell their kidneys would end up doing so--the
argument runs--so this kind of vending is not really a free "choice."
This takes us to yet another recent JME article, by Luke Semrau,
entitled, "The Best Argument Against Kidney Sales Fails."[5] Semrau points
out that there are two types of pressure to tease apart here: a specific
pressure to sell one's kidney (or to engage in prostitution), which would
in fact be directly coercive--and which could conceivably be relieved by
prohibiting the activity in question--and a more general kind of pressure
(i.e., economic insecurity), which, by contrast, could actually be
relieved by any number of activities, including not only selling one's
kidney or engaging in prostitution, but also other types of employment.
In this latter case, however, prohibiting the activities in question
does not actually relieve the more general pressure. Instead, it may
actually compound it--because it would take away otherwise viable
employment options. So, if someone has another way of relieving their
poverty apart from kidney-vending or prostitution (or collecting garbage,
or cleaning toilets, or filling out spreadsheets, or flipping burgers)--
but regards one of those options as being preferable to the alternatives--
then it's hard to see how we could say that they had been specifically
pressured into choosing that career.
Harm and prohibition
All of which is to say the following. Even we if were to grant the
first point from Thomsen's argument--the one that says that prostitution
causes at least some intrinsic harm to prostitutes--this wouldn't
necessarily mean that we should favor a ban on prostitution. For one
thing, if Moen is right, a ban might actually increase the level of harm
to prostitutes, compared against the alternative policy of not having a
ban, and setting up reasonable health and safety regulations, encouraging
de-stigmatization, etc. And for another thing, as Thomsen himself points
out, even if a ban did not have this harmful effect, we might still have
other reasons to argue against it.
For example, we might endorse what Thomsen calls the "antipaternalist
challenge." This view holds that "prohibition constitutes an unjustifiable
interference in the freedom of consenting adults" ([1], p. 454). Peter de
Marneffe[6] puts the view like this:
"Discretionary control over one's own sexual activity [is] central to
sexual autonomy, [to] control over one's body, and so to personal
autonomy. ... It is important that adults have the discretion to make
personal choices about the kind of sex they engage in with other adults,
even if these choices are unwise. So it is objectionable for the
government to prohibit a person for using her own body and sexuality for
prostitution." (quoted in [1], p. 454).
As it happens, I tend to agree with this kind of analysis.[7, 8, 9,
10] Just think: adults are allowed to have sex with someone they might
find otherwise unappealing in exchange for almost anything they desire
except cash: promises of emotional support, the prospect of economic
security, or maybe just a few drinks at the bar. This doesn't mean that
those are good reasons to engage in sexual intercourse--but it's up to
each of us how we negotiate our needs and desires.
More generally, however, when it comes to prohibition, one has to
remember that it is no small step from (on the one hand) getting one's
ethical analysis in order--in terms of establishing if a given practice is
in fact harmful, and in what particular way--to (on the other hand)
determining what kinds of social and legal changes would best reduce the
harm in question, with the least amount of collateral damage.[11]
To put it simply, prohibition is often a bad idea, even if the
targeted activity is harmful.[12]
Back to Thomsen
Thomsen actually appears to agree with this. So, after taking several
pages to try to convince us that prostitution can plausibly be regarded as
bad (because it is at least somewhat intrinsically harmful), and that the
best arguments to the contrary are not as strong as they may seem--he
nevertheless concludes that the "case for [actual] prohibition is murkier
and weaker than its proponents sometimes suggest" ([1], p. 455). A mere
three sentences later, however, Thomsen shifts gears rather awkwardly and
asks us to go ahead and just "assume for the sake of argument that the
balance of reasons favours a general prohibition of prostitution" (ibid)!
Presumably, this is so that Thomsen can set up his case for the
advisability of an exception to an overall ban. He points to two facts
that lay the groundwork for his position:
(1) Many or most persons have a sexuality that generates strong needs
for sexual relations, and
(2) Some disabled persons are partially or entirely incapable of
satisfying this need except through the purchase of sexual services from a
prostitute. ([1], p. 455)
Buying sex--for people with disabilities only?
Let me give you an example of what he means. Quoting from another
source,[13] he cites the case of a man who "couldn't walk and his carer
would bring him. You had to lift him out of the wheelchair and into the
Jacuzzi and he was stiff because he didn't move his arms or legs. He
couldn't move, could get an erection but that was about it" ([1], p. 455).
Evidently, in exchange for money, someone was willing to have sex
with this man under the stated conditions, and this was helpful for
resolving his "needs for sexual relations." (Note that Ezio Di Nucci has
suggested a very interesting alternative: namely, establishing non-profit
charities whose members would voluntarily provide sexual pleasure to the
severely disabled.[14] For a related story, see the fascinating
autobiographical account, "Head Nurses" by William Peace in Atrium
magazine.)[15]
What should we say about a case like this? The first thing to point
out is that the man's disability didn't make it so that he physically
couldn't have sex (if that were the case, hiring a prostitute would not
help his situation); instead, the issue was more that he couldn't find a
willing sexual partner ... for whatever reason.
Now, it seems reasonable to conclude that--in this particular
instance--the "reason" had something to do with his physical disability.
In other words, it seems likely that (all else being equal) relatively few
people would desire, as their first choice, to form a sexual relationship
with someone who could not "move his arms or legs" (although I imagine
that there are many exceptions). This is for the simple reason that some,
presumably enjoyable, sexual experiences are only possible if it is the
case that one's partner can make use of his external limbs without
assistance.
But that is a very specific issue--and it glosses over a more general
point. And that is that all sorts of people find it difficult to find a
willing sexual partner--or enough willing sexual partners--to "satisfy"
their sexual needs, for a whole range of reasons that have nothing to do
with physical (or mental) disability of the "obvious" kind exemplified by
this man. They may simply be perceived as unattractive. Or they may be
shy. Alternatively, they may be very attractive--and not at all shy--and
just have an insatiable sexual appetite. Are all of these people
"disabled" on Thomsen's account?
Defining disability
It's hard to tell. On the one hand, Thomsen could define "disability"
in a very narrow sense that captures only the "obvious" cases that
everyone would recognize--perhaps typified by the man in the example. But
this would result in an extremely unreliable, and indeed almost absurdly
arbitrary proxy for the "real" underlying issue at stake, which is the
difficulty that some people have in finding a willing sexual partner(s)
sufficient to meet their sexual needs without having recourse to
prostitutes.
After all, innumerable people with physical and/or mental
disabilities have extremely satisfying sexual relationships, so the
connection between "having a disability" (of some kind) and "being
perceived as sexually unappealing" is so tangential as to be almost
offensive.
On the other hand, Thomsen has the option of defining "disability" in a
very broad sense--which is what he does in fact choose to do--which
carries its own set of problems. For one thing, it refers to an extremely
vague and amorphous group of people who (to quote from Thomsen's
definition) have "an anomalous physical or mental condition that, given
[their] social circumstances, sufficiently limits [their] possibilities of
exercising [their] sexuality, including fulfilling [their] sexual needs"
([1], p. 455).
But that could include just about anyone! For one thing, there is the
nearly boundless room for interpretation surrounding most of the key terms
in Thomsen's definition: "anomalous," "physical," "mental," "condition,"
"sufficiently," and "fulfill." For example, what is "anomalous" - ?
Statistically rare? How rare? As measured along what dimension? Also, why
should the condition have to be "anomalous" in any event? Isn't it the
(lack of) functional outcome that is the morally relevant concern here?
Or think about the word "condition" - meaning what? Is shyness (to
repeat that example) a "mental condition" that counts as a disability? And
what about "sufficiently"? How shall we determine the cut-off? In other
words, just how "hard" does it have to be to find a willing sexual partner
before one is allowed to register oneself as "sexually disabled," say, and
pick up her "prostitution exemption" card? And finally--"fulfill."
Wouldn't, say, most married couples report that their sexual needs were
not "fulfilled" in some relevant way? Indeed, one survey puts the figure
at 57%.[16]
Conclusion
So this doesn't seem to be the way to go. Either the definition of
disability is so narrow as to be unjustifiably arbitrary as a proxy for
the real underlying moral issue, or it's so broad as to include almost
anyone. Why not--instead--just argue against a general prohibition, and
let mature individuals decide for themselves (a) what kind of consensual
sex they wish to engage in, and (b) in exchange for what.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Julian Savulescu, John Danaher, Michael Hauskeller, Daniel
Goldberg, and Ole Martin Moen for feedback on these ideas. This paper is
adapted from a blog post with the same title originally published at the
Journal of Medical Ethics Blog, available here:
http://blogs.bmj.com/medical-ethics/2015/06/17/prostitution-harm-and-
disability/. Although most of the text is identical to that in the blog
post, I have made some minor improvements to the text in terms of both
style and content. Please note that Dr. Moen and I are preparing a formal
academic paper expanding on the ideas presented in this e-letter, and that
some passages are expected to overlap substantially.
References
[1] Thomsen, F. K. (2015). Prostitution, disability and prohibition.
Journal of Medical Ethics, 41(6), 451-459.
[2] Moen, O. M. (2014). Is prostitution harmful? Journal of Medical
Ethics, 40(2), 73-81.
[3] Vanwesenbeeck, I. (2005). Burnout among female indoor sex
workers. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 34(6), 627-639.
[4] Weinberg, J., de Marneffe, P., Demetriou, D., Earp, B. D.,
Fuller, L., Gauthier, J., Hay, C., Marino, P., Pettit, P., & Whisnant,
R. (2015). Philosophers on prostitution's decriminalization. Daily Nous.
Available at http://dailynous.com/2015/08/13/philosophers-on-prostitutions
-decriminalization/.
[5] Semrau, L. (2015). The best argument against kidney sales fails.
Journal of Medical Ethics, 41(6), 443-446.
[6] de Marneffe, P. (2009). Liberalism and prostitution. Oxford
University Press.
[7] Vierra, A., & Earp, B. D. (2015). Born this way? How high-
tech conversion therapy could undermine gay rights. The Conversation.
Available at https://www.academia.edu/12055156/Born_this_way_How_high-
tech_conversion_therapy_could_undermine_gay_rights.
[8] Earp, B. D. (in press). Female genital mutilation and male
circumcision: Toward an autonomy-based ethical framework. Medicolegal and
Bioethics, in press. Available at
https://www.academia.edu/10270196/Female_genital_mutilation_and_male_circumcision_Toward_an_autonomy
-based_ethical_framework.
[9] Earp, B. D., Sandberg, A., & Savulescu, J. (2014). Brave new
love: The threat of high-tech "conversion" therapy and the bio-oppression
of sexual minorities. AJOB Neuroscience, 5(1), 4-12.
[10] Maslen, H., Earp, B. D., Cohen Kadosh, R., & Savulescu, J.
(2014). Brain stimulation for treatment and enhancement in children: An
ethical analysis. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8(953), 1-5.
[11] Earp, B. D. (2014). Things I have learned (so far) about how to
do practical ethics. Practical Ethics. University of Oxford. Available at
http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2014/03/things-ive-learned-so-far-
about-how-to-do-practical-ethics/.
[12] Earp, B. D. (2013). The ethics of infant male circumcision.
Journal of Medical Ethics, 39(7), 418-420.
[13] Sanders, T. (2007). The politics of sexual citizenship:
commercial sex and disability. Disability & Society, 22(5), 439-455.
[14] Di Nucci, E. (2011). Sexual rights and disability. Journal of
Medical Ethics, 37(3), 158-161.
[15] Peace, W. (2014). Head nurses. Atrium, Winter, 12, 20-22.
[16] National Survey of Marital Strengths. Available at
https://www.prepare-
enrich.com/pe_main_site_content/pdf/research/national_survey.pdf.
Dignity need not be coupled with theology. The South African offence
of 'crimen injuria' is the offence defined as the act of "unlawfully,
intentionally and seriously impairing the dignity of another."
It is based on the 'Latin phrase crimen iniuriae, which should mean
'accusation of abusive behaviour' (
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Crimen_injuria ).
The search for an understanding of a secular basis...
Dignity need not be coupled with theology. The South African offence
of 'crimen injuria' is the offence defined as the act of "unlawfully,
intentionally and seriously impairing the dignity of another."
It is based on the 'Latin phrase crimen iniuriae, which should mean
'accusation of abusive behaviour' (
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Crimen_injuria ).
The search for an understanding of a secular basis for the notion of
'dignity' could benefit from an examination of Roman and South African
case law.
The word itself goes back to the Roman 'dignitas', a strongly related
notion, that also may be worth examining to gain a secular picture
(https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Dignitas_(Roman_concept) ).
This article ( http://athensdialogues.chs.harvard.edu/cgi-
bin/WebObjects/athensdialogues.woa/wa/dist?dis=22 ) on three types of
dignity considers, inter alia, the Ancient Greek model, which would have
informed the Roman.
In support of the universality of the notion if dignity, it is wirth
noting that it also appears in the Chinese and Japanese constitutions:
http://www.chinahumanrights.org/cshrs/Developments/t20130206_1037860.htm
The specific question of how dignity relates to the treatment of the
dead is, I think, related, but separate. A corpse, in Roman law, is a res
nullius, a thing that belongs to nobody, which attracts only duties, not
rights. Organ transplant from corpses, of course, complicates this because
a human organ can be possessed, and has value, possibly even monetary
value, but this does not relate to dignity.
The inarticulate, or instinctive, belief, or feeling, that corpses
are special, and must be treated with respect, relates more to the notion
of the 'sacred', which also exists in a secular sense. This sense relates
to aesthesics and sentimental preciousness, rather than to dedication to
the gods, but is a real and important human universal.
The question of the treatment of the deceased might be considered as
part of the wider question of what, in a secular world, is sacred - a
question that most certainly does not have the answer 'nothing'.
This represents a thoughtful analysis of costly drugs. Recently, the
potential overpricing of a device that allows safe bystander delivery of
the established staple narcotic antagonist naloxone bears closer
examination. As an emergency physician, I am cautious to avoid needle
stick injuries when reversing overdoses in patients who are at high risk
of HIV or hepatitis B/C. No matter how careful one is, the clinician still...
This represents a thoughtful analysis of costly drugs. Recently, the
potential overpricing of a device that allows safe bystander delivery of
the established staple narcotic antagonist naloxone bears closer
examination. As an emergency physician, I am cautious to avoid needle
stick injuries when reversing overdoses in patients who are at high risk
of HIV or hepatitis B/C. No matter how careful one is, the clinician still
incurs significant occupational exposure. I once accidentally stabbed
myself in the hand with a central line finder needle used to treat a
shocked woman with hepatitis C who became acutely agitated after naloxone.
Months of distress and serological testing followed. Economic analyses of
medical care should include safety concerns of frontline paramedics,
police and hospital staff. Expensive non intravenous and non intramuscular
devices that allow the opiate dependent patient to breath effectively
reduces bystander and occupational exposures to life changing infections
and could avert the need to transport to hospital emergency rooms.
There is no doubt that cost effectiveness assessment of medical and
surgical treatment improves the distribution of limited health care
spending more equitably across a range of competing demands for funding.
As adjudicated by patient focused outcomes (and now clinician safety),
these analyses maximize overall health maintenance and gain in society by
ensuring that scarce resources are deployed to patient cohorts that will
attain the most benefit from a moderate to expensive intervention. The
focus goes beyond living longer to living better with enhanced quality of
life, social engagement, symptom and pain control and sustaining emotional
wellbeing, factors important in cancer care.
Further steps are required to exert material influence on how health
dollars could be better spent. Publicly funded clinical trials could be
obliged to examine and report cost implications of health gains when a
treatment proves to be effective. Medical school curricula and residency
programs should emphasize cost effectiveness assessment as much as the
magnitude of therapeutic benefit. Clinical practice guidelines
promulgated by specialist groups need to be rid of industry sponsors that
bias recommendations towards favoring new expensive treatments that are no
better than established options. It is also high time that we also
critically appraise the health impact and cost-overruns from excessive and
inappropriate medical and screening tests ordered by doctors with a vested
interest in using them as much as possible.
Obesity being designated a disease recognizes its adverse effects on
physical and psychological health. Pleas on behalf of the corpulent to not
being judged and regarded without compassion are timely. However,
obesity's classification as a disease could devolve the self-control
needed to assume personal responsibility for the unhealthy dietary and
sedentary choices we make. Dieting, weight consciousness, anxiety about
bo...
Obesity being designated a disease recognizes its adverse effects on
physical and psychological health. Pleas on behalf of the corpulent to not
being judged and regarded without compassion are timely. However,
obesity's classification as a disease could devolve the self-control
needed to assume personal responsibility for the unhealthy dietary and
sedentary choices we make. Dieting, weight consciousness, anxiety about
body weight/shape and widespread hostility to obesity are fundamental
themes in contemporary life. There is tension between trying to control
our body weight in the midst of unprecedented access to unhealthy foods.
The impulse to ridicule and publicly monitor the body shape has its basis
in the highly visible markers of overweight transgressing aesthetic
standards and signalling pathology and disease. Seeing fatness leads to
the negative reading of fat bodies. More than ever, judgements about our
own and others' worth is based on the morphological body as compared to
the ideal. Although there is psychological toil from discrimination meted
out to the obese, being insulated from the externally-imposed assessment
of our weightiness imposes the inertial foundation to stay as we are.
There is indeed a fine line between a stern reprimand that could avert a
burgeoning public health disaster and abuse and derision that debases the
esteem of others. Aside from being susceptible to more serious iterations
of a whole range of chronic medical problems, the obese sustain higher
risks of anaesthetic, pregnancy and post operative complications. They are
more difficult to resuscitate in trauma and critical illness. Life-
sustaining procedures such as intubation and central venous access pose an
anatomical challenge. Due to their thickset habitus, even the longest
chest drains could fail to reach large clots pressing on lungs in major
trauma. The treat of loss of life and limb with acute injury and serious
illness could be far more effective message than low grade hazard spread
over years to decades .
pleas on behalf of the corpulent to not being judged and regarded
without compassion by society. Dieting, weight consciousness, anxiety
about body weight/shape and widespread hostilty to obesity are fundamental
themes in contemporary life. There is tension between trying to control
our body weight in the midst of unprecedented access to unhealthy foods.
The impulse to ridicule and publicly monitor the body shape has its basis
in the highly visible markers of overweightedness transgressing aesthetic
standards and signalling pathology and disease. Seeing fatness leads to
the negative reading of fat bodies. More than ever, judgements about our
own and others' worth is based on the morphological body as compared to
the ideal. Shriver rightly protests the psychological toil from
discrimination suffered by the obese. On the other hand, being insulated
from the externally-imposed assessment of our weightiness imposes the
inertial foundation to stay as we are. There is a fine line between a
stern reprimand that could avert a burgeoning public health disaster and
abuse and derision that debases the esteem of others.
Joseph Ting, MBBS MSc (Lond) BMedSc PGDipEpi DipLSTHM FACEM.
Clinical senior lecturer, Division of Anaesthesiology and Critical
Care, University of Queensland Medical School, Brisbane.
Acute Care Programme, Mater Research Institute, The University of
Queensland, and Division of Critical Care and Anaesthesiology, Mater
Health Services, South Brisbane, QLD 4101.
To the Editor:
The threat posed by human "population explosion" goes beyond that capable
of being supported by the earth's diminishing food and natural resources.
The long standing but recently dormant debate on the sustainability of
population growth is an integral topic that complements recent media focus
on global warming and catastrophic weather events. There needs to be
balanced discussion on the societal and health...
To the Editor:
The threat posed by human "population explosion" goes beyond that capable
of being supported by the earth's diminishing food and natural resources.
The long standing but recently dormant debate on the sustainability of
population growth is an integral topic that complements recent media focus
on global warming and catastrophic weather events. There needs to be
balanced discussion on the societal and health impact of overcrowding,
water and food depletion as well as heightened risk of conflict fueled by
competition for limited resources. Beyond mass starvation, environment
degradation, critical destruction of animal habitat and accelerated loss
of biodiversity needs to be foregrounded. When all living beings are
interdependent and inextricably linked, this omission is remiss.
Proponents of human population growth contend the declining impetus
to have children jeopardizes human prosperity and societal well-being. The
dilemma lies in matching the subsidized needs of a burgeoning number of
retirees and the long living elderly (the demand) with children raised to
tax-paying independence (the supply). However, this co-dependency holds
potential to generate an accelerating demand-supply loop. Today's children
will grow old and in turn seek their due from generations raised to adult
productivity that come after them. The cost of raising a child to
independence, an increasingly deferred milestone, is not just met by the
parents and families but also the rest of society.
Exponential human population growth is not just constrained by the
depletion of food stocks and rapid environmental degradation. Although
food production has kept pace with recent population growth through better
yield crops, improved farming practices and more efficient food
distribution, shortage of safe drinking water in many parts of the
inhabited world remains a threat to all life. The successful cultivation
of crops and animals for human consumption are contingent upon adequate
supplies of water. Water is the font of life on earth; no life (including
sources of human food) can take root without it. Indeed we search for it
in outer space as a harbinger of life.
Joseph Ting, MBBS MSc (Lond) BMedSc PGDipEpi DipLSTHM FACEM.
Clinical senior lecturer, Division of Anaesthesiology and Critical
Care, University of Queensland Medical School, Brisbane.
Acute Care Programme, Mater Research Institute, The University of
Queensland, and Division of Critical Care and Anaesthesiology, Mater
Health Services, South Brisbane, QLD 4101.
It does us all well to recognize that despite only a minority of
scientists engaging in dishonest means to achieve academic gains, their
disrepute will unfortunately taint the hard work of the honest majority.
The greater harm will be loss of faith in publicly funded research and the
waste of resources on non-credible work. Provided one evades detection,
contemporary academia's unbridled publish or perish imperative breed...
It does us all well to recognize that despite only a minority of
scientists engaging in dishonest means to achieve academic gains, their
disrepute will unfortunately taint the hard work of the honest majority.
The greater harm will be loss of faith in publicly funded research and the
waste of resources on non-credible work. Provided one evades detection,
contemporary academia's unbridled publish or perish imperative breeds and
rewards ethical lapses, leading to an irreparable breach of trust.
Deliberately misleading research could be unwittingly adopted into
daily life and even be incorporated as detrimental advances in medical
treatment, putting all of us at risk. The issue should be deemed to go
beyond research misconduct to the material risk of harming people. This
occurs by giving false hope, patients receiving non-beneficial treatment
and forgoing therapies that do work, and incurring unnecessary side-
effects. When standards are not adhered to, we depend on personal ethics
and morals to avoid research misconduct. It is high time that all
researchers were trained in ethical approaches to career advancement,
preferably in their formative years.
Science fetishes the published paper as the gold medal of prestige
and achievement, more so if it is headline grabbing, hosted in a top
journal and concentrates on a hot topic such as sex and race. The perverse
academic promotion and incentive system that view high-profile journals as
the pinnacle of success corrupt us by rewarding those who cut corners, or
worse, cheat for a shot at glory. The pressure to publish or perish has
become the sole currency of tenure, grants, prestige and promotion. The
scientific endeavour is dysfunctional with cheating in scientific papers
growing ever deeper roots. Recent headlines of misdemeanours suggest
exaggeration, fraud and manipulation to enhance academic standing and
competitive funding have only has gotten worse, or that we are better at
detecting problems that would have gone unnoticed in the past.
Falsified or erroneous results have forced authors and editors to
retract papers from journals whose peer reviewers have failed to detect
conclusion-altering biases and misrepresentations. In the same week that
gay marriage was legalised by popular vote in Ireland, Science retracted a
paper that purportedly showed gay political canvassers to be better at
influencing conservative voters' views on same-sex marriage. Diederik
Stapel's sensational findings that garbage-strewn train platforms made
racial prejudice worse made for great press. The hope that cleaning up our
environment could set free the better angel of our natures was dashed when
a whistle blower revealed the social psychology experiments to have never
taken place. Tilburg University defended him to the last, and Stapel
continues to defend his actions as being driven by "a quest for
aesthetics, for beauty-instead of the truth." Yoshiki Sasai, a senior
author of a 2014 Nature paper that claimed to have developed an easy
method to create multipurpose stem cells, was found hanging in his office
stairwell. Vaccination rates tumbled and a rash of measles cases followed
Andrew Wakefield's published contentions that thiomerisal vaccines could
lead to autism. Wakefield is now in jail and deregistered as a medical
practitioner. Authors submit fake peer reviews under assumed false
identities, often ones they themselves have written in praise of their own
work.
The dog-eat-dog competition to be published in prestigious journals,
weak oversight by supervisors or study monitors, the rush by journals to
publish ground-breaking press-worthy studies, cursory appraisal by
reviewers juggling the demands of their own wor, the secrecy and
unavailability of original data for inspection all lead to sloppy or even
unethical research. However, most researchers are honest to their calling,
despite the career and competitive gains that become their due from
disseminating their work in high profile journals. Of 2 million papers
published each year, only a single paper a day is withdrawn from journals
because of misconduct, ranging from plagiarism to fabrication of results.
If we accept that only 2% of researchers commit deliberate or false
misrepresentation, then 98% of the scientific research remains above
board. However, the rare occurrence of fraud taints the whole scientific
community, incurs loss of public trust on whom most funding depends,
embeds erroneous findings in health care (resulting in patient harm),
incurs the adoption of ineffective social policy and undermines future
research underpinned by false premises.
There are ways to minimise fraud, but it will require changing the
process, from how scientists share their data to how their peers review it
and who is allowed to enforce academic standards. Surveillance and
regulatory oversight, such as that provided by Retraction Watch and Office
of Research Integrity in the United States, police for fraud after it has
occurred. Although sanctions, official reprimand and even jail serve as
deterrents for potential offenders, could the problem be weeded out at an
earlier stage, when a study manuscript is appraised by peer reviewers for
suitability to be published? A journal's peer reviewers are supposed to
detect errors, but they often do not have the critical data needed to
check the findings, nor the time to do so, particularly since they are
seldom paid.
The scientific community clearly needs to build a better safety net,
more so in biomedical research involving human subjects. Institutional
review boards are only delegated to assess and approve a clinical trial
protocol for participant safety and methodological validity, with no remit
to monitor a researcher's adherence to safety standards during the conduct
of the study. Although misrepresentation of findings leading to biased,
exaggerated and fraudulent claims can be discerned by independent re-
evaluation of full outcome data that are made available after publication
of a clinical trial, this process does not protect a patient from harm and
coercion for the duration they are enrolled in a clinical trial.
I have previously advocated for the important role of data monitoring
and safety committees in conferring protection to participants and detect
fraud whilst the trial is in progress. With their in depth understanding
of the study objectives and protocol, as well as access to fully disclosed
results as they accumulate, these committees are well placed to gauge
breaches in safety mechanisms, coercive recruitment and fraudulent
behaviour from the start of a trial to its completion. Data monitoring
committees are independent and widely perceived to be extremely competent.
Using these committees to review and approve the completeness of outcomes
reported before publication would also enhance the trustworthiness and
credibility of clinical studies. The DAMOCLES Study Group recommends that
data monitoring committees "ensure that trial results are published in an
unbiased, correct and timely manner" and that the committee discusses
final data and their interpretation with study investigators. The ability
to monitor for errors, whether deliberate or not, while the study is being
conducted improves the validity and credibility of submitted manuscripts,
eliminates the need for resource intensive post-publication re-evaluation,
and averts disseminating erroneous studies to journal audiences in the
first place.
Dr. Miller cites the "professional integrity of physicians" and the uncertainty of whether additional interventions will restore a patient's desire to live.
Does Dr. Miller's professional integrity include honesty, truthfulness, and sincerity when speaking to severely treatment-resistant patients? Particularly with respect to the efficacy of treatments that will provide rapid response and prolonged remission? D...
Bentham's hedonic, or felicific, calculus doesn't work, in practice, either, so the criticism of a calculus being difficult or not absolute applies equally to utilitarianism.
The hedonic calculus allows conclusions with no benefit, or negative benefit, or positive pain for some. If the net calculation is positive for all, then the negative consequences for one or more individuals is subsumed by the greater good...
In their recent article Farrell and Brazier [1] assert that the recent decision in Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board ...
Abstract
Despite a damning 2014 Australian Human Rights Commission report into the plight of children in immigration detention, the disturbing findings of reported in the 2015 Moss Inquiry into allegations relating to conditions and circumstances at the Australian regional migrant processing centre in Nauru, and compelling evidence of the harm suffered by these children, Australia continues to hold children in im...
Brian D. Earp University of Oxford
Introduction
Is prostitution harmful? And if it is harmful, should it be illegal to buy (or sell) sexual services? And if so, should there ever be any exceptions? What about for people with certain disabilities--say--who might find it difficult or even impossible to find a sexual partner if they weren't allowed to exchange money for sex? Do people have a "right" to s...
Dignity need not be coupled with theology. The South African offence of 'crimen injuria' is the offence defined as the act of "unlawfully, intentionally and seriously impairing the dignity of another."
It is based on the 'Latin phrase crimen iniuriae, which should mean 'accusation of abusive behaviour' ( https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Crimen_injuria ).
The search for an understanding of a secular basis...
This represents a thoughtful analysis of costly drugs. Recently, the potential overpricing of a device that allows safe bystander delivery of the established staple narcotic antagonist naloxone bears closer examination. As an emergency physician, I am cautious to avoid needle stick injuries when reversing overdoses in patients who are at high risk of HIV or hepatitis B/C. No matter how careful one is, the clinician still...
Obesity being designated a disease recognizes its adverse effects on physical and psychological health. Pleas on behalf of the corpulent to not being judged and regarded without compassion are timely. However, obesity's classification as a disease could devolve the self-control needed to assume personal responsibility for the unhealthy dietary and sedentary choices we make. Dieting, weight consciousness, anxiety about bo...
To the Editor: The threat posed by human "population explosion" goes beyond that capable of being supported by the earth's diminishing food and natural resources. The long standing but recently dormant debate on the sustainability of population growth is an integral topic that complements recent media focus on global warming and catastrophic weather events. There needs to be balanced discussion on the societal and health...
It does us all well to recognize that despite only a minority of scientists engaging in dishonest means to achieve academic gains, their disrepute will unfortunately taint the hard work of the honest majority. The greater harm will be loss of faith in publicly funded research and the waste of resources on non-credible work. Provided one evades detection, contemporary academia's unbridled publish or perish imperative breed...
Pages