I am pleased that the Journal of Medical Ethics has dealt with the ethics
of circumcision. Circumcision has a seamy underside of violence and
sexual abuse that can be seen in such disparate sources as the Bible [the
hundred foreskin dowry] (1 Sam. 18:25-27) and the circumcision and
slaughter of the Shechemites (Genesis chapter 34 ) [1]. A...
I am pleased that the Journal of Medical Ethics has dealt with the ethics
of circumcision. Circumcision has a seamy underside of violence and
sexual abuse that can be seen in such disparate sources as the Bible [the
hundred foreskin dowry] (1 Sam. 18:25-27) and the circumcision and
slaughter of the Shechemites (Genesis chapter 34 ) [1]. A similar pattern
of sexual abuse may be observed ethnic-religious conflicts in the Sudan
[2] and Indonesia [3] and in sexually charged sites on the internet such
as Circlist.
However, value based judgments can also be seen in comments from medical
journals and books. Here are two examples:
Williamson and Williamson published a paper on Midwestern American
women¹s preferences for circumcised penises in the Journal of Sexual and
Marital Therapy. They say:
'While the foreskin of an uncircumcised penis can be retracted, the
circumcised penis exists in exposed beauty whether flaccid or erect.' [4] .
The Williamsons are not alone in this sensual admiration. Another doctor
expressed his preferences even more lyrically:
`[C]ircumcision is a beautification comparable to rhinoplasty, and a
circumcised penis appears in its flaccid state as an erect uncircumcised
organ - a beautiful instrument of precise intent' [5].
If doctors can express these preferences so openly in academic journals,
it shows a cultural blindness to signs of a personal preference [personal
involvement] in circumcision. In fact, some bend over backwards not to
accuse others of inappropriate behaviour. Dr Janet Menage gave an account
of man who was circumcised at the age of three who:
...vividly recalled at the age of thirty, how he had been undressed
and his penis manipulated by a man in a mask pre-operatively, without his
consent. The child had experienced an erection about which he was embarrassed, and then, post-operatively found himself with a bleeding,
painful penis from which the foreskin had been amputated without his permission. This event had changed his life. He was angry that this had
been done to him and humiliated by his powerlessness to protect himself
from what felt like sexual manipulation. He felt that he had been
sexually abused. In any other context than the medical one, the same sequence of events would be open to an interpretation of sexual abuse. To
the child, the psychological impact is the same, whether it is illegal
rape or legalised medical activity [6]
So the manipulation of the child's penis to erection merely "felt like"
sexual manipulation, and the man only "felt" that he had been sexually
abused. Thus Doctor Menage avoided accusing even an unnamed doctor of
sexual abuse
Medical boards have had to take action against doctors over circumcision
abuses [7]. I believe that the cultural blindness towards the problematic nature of circumcision [signs of an emotional involvement in
circumcision] raises moral and legal questions that must be addressed more vigorously by medical authorities.
Yours faithfully,
Michael Glass
References
(1) See: Glass, M., What the Bible Reveals About Circumcision and Sexual
Violence http://www.cirp.org/pages/cultural/glass3/
(2) Lindsay Murdoch. Terror attacks in the name of religion. Morning
Herald, Sydney, Saturday, 27 January 2001.
http://old.smh.com.au/news/0101/27/review/review8.html also
http://www.cirp.org/news/morningherald01-27-01/
(3) Michael Coren. Sudan's Slaves. Frontpage, Toronto, Ontario, 25
November 2003. http://www.cirp.org/news/frontpage11-25-03/
(4) Williamson ML & Williamson PS. Women's preferences for penile
circumcision in sexual partners. J Sex Marital Ther. 1988;
14(2):8-12.http://www.geocities.com/HotSprings/2754/womenpref.html
(5) Quoted in Preston EN. `Whither the foreskin.' JAMA 1970;
213(11):1853-1858. Preston attributes the quote to `Goodwin, quoted by
Kaufman JJ: Should circumcision be done routinely? Med Aspects Hum Sexual
1:27-28, 1967' (footnote 13 of Preston's article).
(6) Dr Janet Menage MA MB ChB , Circumcision and Psychological Harm
http://www.norm-uk.org/circumcision_psychological_effects.html
The case has been made for environmental influences, which might
reasonably include medications taken as prescribed or consumed in
contaminated water or food, having a profound effect upon future
generations by influencing gamete selection [1].
In the case of obesity, for example, it was proposed that gametes
might be evolutionarily selected to thrive on the diet to which they have
access...
The case has been made for environmental influences, which might
reasonably include medications taken as prescribed or consumed in
contaminated water or food, having a profound effect upon future
generations by influencing gamete selection [1].
In the case of obesity, for example, it was proposed that gametes
might be evolutionarily selected to thrive on the diet to which they have
access. It was further proposed the rise in prevalence of obesity
especially in children might be a direct consequences of parental diet and
even exposure to exhaust fumes upon gamete selection.
In the case of carbon monoxide released in exhaust fumes it was
proposed that inhibition of electron transport in the respiratory chain
might cause the lipid shift in substrate utilisation in oxidative
phosphorylation seen in exercising athletes and responsible for the
biochemical risk factors and obesity associated with an increased risk of
cerebrovascular and coronary artery diseases.
Evidence-based medical care, as opposed to surgical or other
interventional care, is primarily based upon the results of prospective
randomised studies. Many of these have violated the uncertainty principle
and are meaningless [2]. Those that have not are by definition ineffective
and at best have a fine-tuning effect upon short-term outcome in very
clearly defined circumstances. The have an unknown effect upon long-term
outcome and certainly upon gamete selection and the state of future
generations.
There is clearly a difference between medications administered for
short-term gain, medications such as intravenous aminophylline for acute
asthma or penicillin for a streptococcal infection, and those administered
for longer term gain. The former are essential for patient care. The
latter are not. Of particular concern amongst the latter are the tons of
NSAIDS, antidepressants, other psychotropics, and even statins prescribed
all of which may change the way people live and die without improving
outcome from all causes or longevity. All have the potential to impair
mitochondrial function, a particular concern in gamete selection. They may
even have been an importent cause or amplifyer of most of the chronic
diseases we see today in a develpoped opulation [3]. Add to that the host
of over-the-counter medications and herbal remedies that exert little more
than an placebo effect and might have adverse effects on present and
future generations.
Should any medication be prescribed for anything other than for a
very limited duration in a few highly selected acute illnesses, such as
puerperal sepsis or meningococcal septicaemia? If we were to abolish
pharmaceutical treatments for the majority of chronic diseases tomorrow
we would still have many therapeutic options. What is more if reliance for
treatment for chronic disases, such as neurodegenerative diseases, chronic
heart and even pulmonary failure, were to be shifted to hightech and
invasive options there would be an huge incentive for clinicians and blue
chip companies, such as Medtronic, to develop even better and safer
invasive treatments. Unlike pharmaceutical treatments invasive treatments
should not present a risk to future generations if safe industrial and
disposal practices are followed.
So is evidence-base medicine ethical? It is a legitimate and serious
question worthy of consideration. With the projected increase and ageing
of the population the hypothetical risk of having a adverse effect upon
gamete selection could increase greatly. Are we to leave future
generations to decide whether our pharmaceutical interventions have had an
adverse effect upon gamete selection and compromised the future of
humanity?
What then of the evidence-base for invasive practices? I think we
had been doing just fine until over-regulation and seriously misguided if
well-intentioned attempts to enforce lower salaries and clinical pathways
upon clinicians started to destroy the foundations of the profession.
The damage inflicted upon the profession is severe and it may take decades
to recover. Many patients have suffered and many have died unnecessarily.
There can be few better examples of chucking the baby out with the
bathwater.
References
(1) Neither ?
Richard G Fiddian-Green (1 August 2004) eLetter re: Obesity in Britain:
gluttony or sloth?
Prentice and Jebb (12 August 1995)
(2) Proof of the impossible: p<_0.000000001 xmlns:re="urn:x-prefix:re" xmlns:_328="urn:x-prefix:_328" richard="richard" g="g" fiddian-green="fiddian-green" bmj.com="bmj.com" _11="_11" jan="jan" _2004="_2004" eletter="eletter" re:_="re:_" auro="auro" del="del" giglio="giglio" and="and" luciano="luciano" jose="jose" costa="costa" the="the" quality="quality" of="of" randomised="randomised" controlled="controlled" trials="trials" may="may" be="be" better="better" than="than" assumed="assumed" bmj="bmj" _328:_="_328:_" _24-25="_24-25" p="p"/> (3) Iatrogenic diseases with a common cause?
Richard G Fiddian-Green (25 October 2002) eLetter re: Edward H Wagner
and Trish Groves
Care for chronic diseases
BMJ 2002; 325: 913-914
Schaafsma and Verbeek are positive about the central ideas of our
paper, as they endorse what we have named the intrusion and coordination
model. They also regard the notion of coordination of worlds of norms and
values that we develop in the last part, as appropriate for all medical
disciplines and professions.
Their criticism, however, misses the point of the article. Far from
undervaluing occ...
Schaafsma and Verbeek are positive about the central ideas of our
paper, as they endorse what we have named the intrusion and coordination
model. They also regard the notion of coordination of worlds of norms and
values that we develop in the last part, as appropriate for all medical
disciplines and professions.
Their criticism, however, misses the point of the article. Far from
undervaluing occupational medicine, our paper intends to find remedies for
the relative lack of classical clinical evidence based on randomized
clinical trials, and for the lack of ethical vocabularies to study the use
of such evidence. Schaafsma and Verbeek themselves write that the form of
evaluation that is common in occupational health is "very crude [...]
compared to other methods such as evaluation studies or experimental
studies". Their solution for that problem is to 'get in line' with
standard ways of gathering evidence, while we argue that the problems are
too fundamental for that solution to work. Because of the heterogeneity of
orphaned fields of medicine, different models of evaluation and ethical
analysis, not simply more evaluation, is what is needed.
I enjoyed the fable very much, and think that I am in agreement with
much of the philosophical gloss.
There is, however, one issue that troubles me. To kill the dragon of aging
we need not only to develop life extension therapies, we need to develop
immortality therapies. Otherwise there will still be trains going up the
mountain, although for a given population size there will be fewer and
fewer trains...
I enjoyed the fable very much, and think that I am in agreement with
much of the philosophical gloss.
There is, however, one issue that troubles me. To kill the dragon of aging
we need not only to develop life extension therapies, we need to develop
immortality therapies. Otherwise there will still be trains going up the
mountain, although for a given population size there will be fewer and
fewer trains the longer we can extend life.
The author gives us some evidence that life extension is a realistic hope,
but what about immortality (which at least for robust, bodily immortality
implies indestructability)?
Is the dragon slaying rocket likely, or are current efforts more likely to
lead to an anorexic tablet for dragons.
We would like to comment on the recent theme issue on evidence based
medicine, especially on the article about "Coordinating the norms and
values of medical research, medical practice, and patient worlds." This
is a title that appeals to all physicians with an interest in medical
research and its implementation in medical practice. Vos et al. embark
upon the important topic of evidence-based occupa...
We would like to comment on the recent theme issue on evidence based
medicine, especially on the article about "Coordinating the norms and
values of medical research, medical practice, and patient worlds." This
is a title that appeals to all physicians with an interest in medical
research and its implementation in medical practice. Vos et al. embark
upon the important topic of evidence-based occupational health that is the
focus of our own professional activities. In general, we agree with the
core-models in their article: the intrusion model and the collaboration
model. Put in other words these models imply that new methods slowly
intrude into the daily practice of health professionals and that
scientific evidence has to be balanced with the preferences of the
patients.
However, we got confused by the content of the article where occupational
health was referred to as an orphaned field of medicine. The authors refer
to orphan field as a model to explain that occupational health hardly has
any scientific evidence to justify its right to exist. In addition it was
argued that occupational health deals mostly with specific syndromes like
repetitive strain injury syndrome (RSI), whiplash and chronic fatigue
syndrome. An extra argument for the claim that occupational health is an
orphaned field of medicine is the idea that treatment of these syndromes
is not substantiated with convincing evidence.
We were very surprised by the logic of the authors. First of all, it
seems at least a logical mistake to take pars pro toto and to identify the
field of occupational health with disorders that have recently come up.
What about the other themes in occupational health such as noise-induced
hearing loss, toxicology, return to work, stress etc.? We would argue that
those disorders mentioned by the authors form only a small part of the
daily reality of occupational health.
Secondly, there is an enormous amount of scientific research on
occupational health issues. Research in occupational health has
concentrated on the causes of ill-health at work and has led to a
substantial body of work on occupational exposure. A Medline search with
the Medical Subject Heading ‘occupational exposure’ yields more than 26
000 references, of which 2984 were classified as reviews and 89 as meta-
analyses. This constitutes a valuable body of evidence on the effects of a
wide range of exposures at work. The findings with regard to work-related
diseases and adverse health effects have been strongly associated with
immediate preventive action laid down in many legal obligations for
employers and employees. For evaluation of these preventive measures we
usually rely on surveillance such as medical or hazard surveillance.
However, this is a very crude form of evaluation compared to other methods
such as evaluation studies or experimental studies. Surveillance does
especially not provide a comparison of preventive methods which would
enable a conclusion about the most effective preventive interventions. To
that end more detailed evaluation studies or experimental studies are
needed. It is acknowledged that more and better research is needed on
interventions for occupational health, but the same applies to other
medical disciplines. Recently, occupational health has actually been given
its own field within the Cochrane Collaboration showing that worldwide
occupational health is acknowledged as an important medical discipline and
that its interventions form an important part of health care.[1]
Thirdly, we disagree that the mentioned complex syndromes are
typically handled within occupational health. From our perspective, these
syndromes are at least as frequently encountered within other medical
disciplines like neurology, orthopaedics, internal medicine and last but
not least general medicine. We do agree that RSI is frequently encountered
by occupational physicians and that objective criteria for the diagnosis
are still disputed. However, this is more a matter of semantics than a
real lack of consensus. If we use a more precise definition of work-
related upper limb disorders there seems to be consensus about the
criteria.[2] There is also consensus among Dutch occupational physicians
about diagnosis and treatment according to their recent evidence based
guideline.[3] It would have strengthened the argument of the authors if
they had put some effort in systematically searching the literature on the
important topics of their article such as occupational health,
occupational medicine and repetitive strain injury. Now, we get the
feeling that they have used what was available and suited their discourse.
Finally, we would like to express our consent on the proposed
coordination model, especially the part about “A more symmetrical and
deliberative relationship between professionals and patients”. We think
this is appropriate for all medical disciplines and professionals.
References
(1) Verbeek JHAM et al. Building an evidence base for occupational
health interventions. Scand J Work Environ Health 2004; 30(2): 164-168
(2) Sluiter JK et al. Criteria document for evaluating the work-
relatedness of upper-extremity musculoskeletal disorders. Scand J Work
Environ Health. 2001;27 Suppl 1:1-102.
(3) Verbeek JHAM et al. Nek- en schouderklachten en RSI. (Practice
guideline for occupational physicians; Management of workers with hand,
neck and shoulder complaints (RSI)). 2003. Nederlandse Vereniging voor
Arbeids- en Bedrijfsgeneeskunde (The Dutch Association for Occupational
Medicine).
"Informed consent is a great advance towards protecting the rights and autonomy of patients.
However its usefulness is far from universal: informed consent cannot clarify the secondary use of tissues, as the authors point out, and in practice its use is more and more a manner of legal protection against malpractice claims in various countries, and a virtual nonentity in emergency situations,
"Informed consent is a great advance towards protecting the rights and autonomy of patients.
However its usefulness is far from universal: informed consent cannot clarify the secondary use of tissues, as the authors point out, and in practice its use is more and more a manner of legal protection against malpractice claims in various countries, and a virtual nonentity in emergency situations,
We cannot forget that some institutions give a patient, two days before a cardiac surgery, for example, four or five books of medical texts. As the authors point out, we never will acquire a proper, ethical, real informative and honest form an informed consent that is valid in all fields."
I want to thank Dr Olivieri’s core set of long-standing supporters for their letter [1] on the Introduction to the Olivieri Symposium that was recently published in the Journal of Medical Ethics.[2] Gallie et al. have been staunch supporters of Dr. Olivieri for years, and this support on her behalf has played a pivotal role in attempting to clarify perceived mistakes made in public and academic repo...
I want to thank Dr Olivieri’s core set of long-standing supporters for their letter [1] on the Introduction to the Olivieri Symposium that was recently published in the Journal of Medical Ethics.[2] Gallie et al. have been staunch supporters of Dr. Olivieri for years, and this support on her behalf has played a pivotal role in attempting to clarify perceived mistakes made in public and academic reporting on the Olivieri Affair.
In their recent letter, however, there are a number of plainly false charges that demonstrate either they have not read the Introduction closely enough or that their letter was hastily written (or possibly both). Gallie et al. charge that several events of fundamental ethical concern were left out of the Introduction and the authors accept some facts that are highly questionable. The purpose of this response is to clarify the errors and falsities within Gallie et al's letter. I also highlight the few points of legitimate disagreement they raise.
1. The Purpose of the Symposium Introduction
The time line within the Introduction was included to provide readers unfamiliar with the Olivieri Affair with a snapshot of key events, not a systematic recounting of all events (as was noted). The purpose of the Introduction was always descriptive and informational in nature, and not concerned with putting forth normative arguments or conclusions. We invited leading bioethicists and individuals involved and/or familiar with the Olivieri Affair to address the ethical questions and issues surrounding and arising from this case.
Gallie et al. charge that “Most surprisingly, they have fallen into a common error: emphasising the scientific argument, when that is not their expertise, and bypassing the fundamental ethical issue of the obligation to put concern for safety first.” This charge is largely unfounded. Firstly, the Introduction did not bypass the fundamental ethical issue in favour of emphasizing the scientific argument – in fact, we state the Olivieri Affair was “much more than a scientific disagreement over the interpretation of data” ([2], p.5). Secondly, the Introduction does discuss the ethical obligations to put safety first and support researchers in Olivieri's position – we clearly do on page 6 of the Introduction.[2] However, as was previously stated, we invited contributors to address what they saw as the fundamental ethical issues in the case; it was not the Introduction’s function to do this. (I address the issue of scientific arguments and expertise in §7).
Gallie et al. think it ought to be concluded in a grand, sweeping fashion that “Thus their account both misleads in historical fact and misses the ethical point”. Not only is this leap in logic specious, as will be demonstrated throughout this response, the Introduction is not guilty of misleading or missing the point.
2. The Naimark Report
Gallie et al. state that the Introduction failed to give the central conclusion of the Naimark Report[3], while the CAUT [4] and CPSO [5] Reports were given. In the time line, we state that the Naimark report finds that the HSC staff did not act improperly ([2], p. 5, see time line heading ‘December 1998’). This was the primarily conclusion of focus in the public reporting of the issue. However, Gallie et al. believe we should have also reported the fact that the Naimark Report declared that Dr Olivieri had failed to comply with her ethical obligations. They claim “this central finding of the Naimark report was the basis of HSC’s strong actions against Dr Olivieri during the next three years. It fueled the controversy from then onward, and the post-1998 story would be incomprehensible to a reader of JME who was unaware of it”. We chose to leave this out because other contributors to the symposium make this point explicitly.[6] Upon reflection, maybe this should have been made more explicit in the Introduction. However, Gallie et al's contention that the post-98 story would be incomprehensible to a reader who was unaware of the Olivieri Affair seems over dramatic. While this finding should have been more explicit, the overall time line is quite comprehensible to those unfamiliar with the case.
Nevertheless, Gallie et al. go on to deride the Naimark Report and maintain “Naimark’s conclusions are strongly refuted by the CAUT and CPSO reports”. It is claimed that we failed to reference Naimark's discredited findings by the CAUT and CPSO reports. This is true, however, we also failed to reference those who have sought to discredit the findings of the CAUT report. The time line was complied using documents in the public domain and we attempted to provide the best accounting possible; such an attempt could not be reasonably expected to provide a systematic historical account (for arguments against the possibility of determining ‘historical facts’, see Jenkins [7]). When we did use the Naimark Report, the information used was on the whole cross-referenced with other documents in the public domain.
Gallie et al. seem to resent the appearance that all three reports used in the Introduction are of equal probative value. No such representations were made or intended, but I can see why they may think this is the case. They cite the controversy surrounding the Naimark Report as evidence of why it should not be viewed as worthwhile as the CAUT and CPSO reports. However, it seems far from obvious that since these reports discredit the conclusions of the Naimark Report that all of the information contained therein is false. We encouraged readers to look at all the reports. Personally, I believe the CAUT report is a much better and balanced report. However, just because the CAUT report says that the Naimark Report came to erroneous conclusions does not make it the case that the report should not be referenced at all. Given that we state that the Hospital for Sick Children and the University of Toronto should have done more to support Dr. Olivieri, one might infer that we tended to believe the CAUT report was better than the Naimark report. But again, it was not the purpose of the Introduction to make pronouncements on which report was better. If the specific information used from the Naimark Report is false (all incidences of the use of the Naimark Report are referenced), please inform the JME and an amendment or retraction can be made. Chastising us for not rejecting the entire report, and everything contained in it, is not sufficient to reasonably ground a charge that time line is misleading in historical fact.
3. The College of Physicians and Surgeons (Ontario) Report
In the Introduction, we reported that College of Physicians and Surgeons (Ontario) [CPSO] report determined that Dr Olivieri was found to have done nothing wrong in her role as investigator of the L1 trial. This report arose out of a complaint from a physician at the Hospital for Sick Children against Dr. Olivieri. While the CPSO report dealt with a great deal of the events of the Olivieri Affair, it was not a report or inquiry into the entire Olivieri Affair per se (i.e. the scope of the CPSO committee was to investigate the charge against Dr Olivieri, not conduct a review of all events in the Olivieri Affair).
Gallie et al. claim that we should have also reported the further fact that the CPSO found Dr Olivieri’s conduct “exemplary”. I take Gallie et al’s (implicit?) point that having been found to have done nothing wrong and being found to have acted in an exemplary fashion are different enough to merit mention. We choose to leave this out because other contributors to the symposium make this point explicitly.[6] Maybe it was an oversight not to include this laudatory epithet and only to report that Dr. Olivieri was found to have done nothing wrong. Personally, I believe Dr Olivieri acted in an exemplary fashion and showed extreme courage and moral fortitude. So, the absence of the word exemplary from our discussion of the CPSO report was honestly inadvertent. Nevertheless, it would be wrong to claim that the Introduction did not give the impression that Dr Olivieri acted in an exemplary fashion. We state that Dr Olivieri had great conviction in standing up and speaking out against the academic medical complex ([2], p.6).
4. Dr Koren
Gallie et al. claim that we were wrong to state that Dr Olivieri received “two letters” from Dr. Koren because “these two ‘letters’ have been discussed in three separate wider-ranging inquiries, each casting serious doubt on their authenticity and citing evidence that they were not written on the 1996 and 1997 ‘dates’ they bear, but instead in the fall of 1998. Dr Olivieri never received either letter, and learned of them only after the Naimark report was published. Dr Koren himself later acknowledged that he had destroyed evidence relevant to determining the actual dates on which the ‘letters’ were typed.” We did not refer to these two letters, nor did we imply that Dr Olivieri ever received these two letters when Dr Koren originally reported. We only state that “[Dr Koren] inform[ed] Dr Olivieri that he will not continue in collaborative and data interpretation work with her” ([2], p.4).
Gallie et al. claim we failed to explicitly report that Dr. Koren in later publishing findings that L1 was effective and safe on a re-analysis of data and that was failed to state that “these 1997 publications had been drafted by Apotex staff and he had agreed to be listed as senior author. This was a year in which Dr Koren held a $250,000 research grant from Apotex, but he did not disclose in these publications that he was funded by Apotex, nor did he disclose to the university the source or purpose of the grant”. Again, we made no representations as to the validity of Dr. Koren’s research. We merely reported that he published these findings. Indeed, the aforementioned information provides good cause to be concerned over issues of conflict of interest. However, since we did not make or imply that this research invalidated or called into question Dr. Olivieri’s findings, it was felt that we could not make room for this further information. Moreover, given the subsequent treatment of Dr Koren (i.e., being disciplined over professional and research behaviour), it is unlikely one would think that Dr Koren’s research would invalidate Dr Olivieri’s findings simply on reporting that contrary findings were published.
Gallie et al. also claim that “the Time line does not mention that Dr Koren was disciplined for professional misconduct by the CPSO (as well as by the hospital and the university)”. This is simply false. In fact, the Introduction states that Dr. Koren was disciplined by the Hospital for Sick Children and the University of Toronto, in addition to being cautioned (which is a form of discipline) by the CPSO ([2], see, p.5, time line heading ‘1999/2000’). It is incorrect and misleading to say that this information was omitted from the Introduction.
It was an inadvertent omission that we did not include the fact that Dr Koren was disciplined again by the University of Toronto for scientific misconduct in connection with a 1999 journal article favorable to L1. As was stated at the end of the time line, any omissions were unintentional. However, it seems that this minor omission is not crucial for the general picture a reader unfamiliar with the case needed to know, given we did mention that Dr. Koren was disciplined by the Hospital for Sick Children, the University of Toronto (the first time), and the College of Physicians and Surgeons (Ontario).
5. Apotex’s Legal Warnings/Threats Against Dr Olivieri
Gallie et al. charge “The Time line does not mention that Apotex sent a whole series of legal warnings”. This is simply false. In fact, we mention these legal warnings on three separate occasions. Examination of the time line will reveal that we indicate:
a) the initial legal warning Apotex made against Dr Olivieri,
b) a subsequent legal threat made by Michael Spino, and
c) Dean Aberman’s request to Apotex to stop their legal threats ([2], see p.3, time line headings ‘May 1996’ and ‘June 1996’). It is incorrect and misleading to say that this information was omitted from the Introduction.
6. The Relationship Between Apotex and the University of Toronto
Gallie et al. charge that “The Time line also omits that, simultaneously, the university and Apotex were in negotiations for a multimillion-dollar donation to enable the university to build a new biomedical science”. Because of space considerations we choose to present this information not in the timeline, but in section III of the Introduction. In fact, we explicitly state in the Introduction that ‘…at the time of the Olivieri Affair, Apotex was in discussions with the University of Toronto about a multimillion dollar donation’ ([2], p.6). Moreover, in the same section, we also explicitly state the involvement of the president of the university with Apotex. We state that “… the president of the University of Toronto had lobbied the Prime Minister of Canada on behalf of Apotex in 1999 [and] there was a major outcry and further talk of distrust of close ties between public institutions and corporate interests” ([2], p.6).
If the crux of Gallie et al’s complaint is that this information should have appeared in the time line and not in the next section of the Introduction, it would seem that such a complaint is trivial and unreasonable. What is of importance is that this information was included in the Introduction. It is simply erroneous and misleading to give the impression that such information was omitted from the Introduction.
7. Providing Information about a Disease in a Bioethics Article
Gallie et al. seem to find it problematic that the Introduction included basic scientific information about thalassemia (for the purposes of informing those readers who may not be familiar with the disease). The problem seems to stem from the fact that the Introduction was not written by scientific experts in the disease, and somehow this fact is supposed to relate to "fudging the ethics".
Firstly, we never claimed to be experts on thalassemia (although one of the authors does have a medical degree). The purpose of including such information was to provide general, background information about the disease, its treatment, and the impetus for the research for an oral iron chelator. In reality, Gallie et al’s mention (on two occasions) that the authors of the Introduction are not experts in thalassemia is a fallacious attempt to discredit the Introduction without warrant. (It is an instance of an argumentum ad verecundiam fallacy, for those interested in logic). The fact that the authors are not experts in thalassemia has absolutely no baring on the putative errors Gallie et al. seem to find with the Introduction. It would be just as silly for me to argue that since Gallie et al. are not moral experts or possess a PhD in philosophy that they should not be able to comment on ethical matters. Now, if there is an error about the scientific information included that is grossly misleading about thalassemia and its treatment, then that would be an issue worthy of mention and deserving correction. However, since they fail to mention any such errors one can only assume that this is not the source of the problem.
Secondly, it does not follow that one needs to be a scientific expert to provide general information on a disease or its treatment. We were not providing expert opinion on the topic. We were not making pronouncements about an issue where thalassemia experts in the field disagree or where there is a high level of uncertainty. In fact, in this information we cite Dr Olivieri’s work, and one of her supporters, Dr David Weatherall, as authorities in the field. If the inclusion of basic, background information about a disease in the context of a bioethics article is problematic, many bioethicists are certainly guilty of this!
8. Omitting the “Fundamental Ethics Issue”
Gallie et al. conclude their letter by returning to the alleged omission that we did not mention the “fundamental ethical issue”, viz., informed consent and patient safety. If one examines the concluding paragraph of the Introduction, we covered all of the issues Gallie et al. say we omitted.
Gallie et al. state “Dr Olivieri identified a risk of lack of sustained efficacy and therefore possible harm, and insisted on informed patient consent and valid clinical trials to address the potential harms.” In fact, we acknowledge this to be the case ([2], pp. 2-3, time line heading ‘March 1996’). This information was not omitted from the Introduction.
Gallie et al. also state “Apotex prematurely terminated the trials and repeatedly tried to silence her with legal warnings”. In fact, we also acknowledge this to be the case ([2], pp. 2-3). This information was not omitted from the Introduction.
Gallie et al. conclude that “The fundamental ethical issue is the failure of Dr Olivieri’s hospital and university to support her ethically correct approach to clinical science.” In section III, we state that ‘HSC and U of T should have supported Dr Olivieri more... and protected her ability to do what she thought (and had sufficient warrant to believe) was required by a morally responsible researcher’ ([2], p.6). Although we tried to deal only with descriptive matters in the Introduction (leaving the evaluative judgments for contributors), even we could not resist making this conclusion. I am unsure as to why Gallie et al. fail to see it.
9. Concluding Remarks
We certainly welcome more input from those individuals involved with the Olivieri Affair. As it states in the Introduction, “there are many lessons to be learnt from the Olivieri Affair. We hope this symposium will begin a fair and productive examination of these which will lead to better ethical evaluation and regulation of research, not just in North America but globally” ([2], p.6). However, what is quite unhelpful is input that asserts demonstrably false and misleading accusations. No one benefits from this. That being said, Gallie et al. do raise a few legitimate points that will be of interest to those interested in the Olivieri Affair (I have noted where I believe these few points have been made). I thank them for elucidating these points. It is the rest of their letter, however, I find of little value.
According to the Oxford English Dictionary, a symposium is a “meeting or conference for discussion of some subject; hence, a collection of opinions delivered, or a series of articles contributed, by a number of persons on some special topic” [8]. However, it is more than this. A symposium, an institution dating back at least to ancient Greece, is not merely a collection of opinions on the same topic, but a co-operative attempt to engage in dialogue to elucidate the problem or issues under consideration. It is foolhardy to think one could isolate individual components of a symposium as ‘mini-attempts’ to provide a complete picture or answer to all questions or issues. For instance, that would be like reading Plato’s Symposium without reading all of the speeches or reading one of the speeches as being representative of the whole story! Attempting to pull out individual contributions as being disconnected from the whole is to take a wrongheaded view. Taken as a whole, the Olivieri symposium meets its aim of being a fair and productive examination of the events and issues involved. The Introduction contributes to it being so.
References
1. Gallie BL, Durie P, Ranalli P, Dick J, Chan HSL. Introduction to the Olivieri Symposium – Don’t Fudge the Ethics [electronic response to Viens and Savulescu; Introduction to The Olivieri symposium] jmedethics.com 2004http://jme.bmjjournals.com/cgi/eletters/30/1/1#169
2. Viens AM, Savulescu J. Introduction to The Olivieri symposium. J Med Ethics 2004;30(1):1-7.
3. Naimark A, Knoppers B, Lowy F. Clinical trials of L1 (deferiprone) at The Hospital for Sick Children: a review of the facts and circumstances. Toronto: Hospital for Sick Children; 1998.
4. Thompson J, Baird P, Downie J. Report of the Committee of Inquiry on the case involving Dr. Nancy Olivieri, the Hospital for Sick Children, the University of Toronto, and Apotex, Inc. Toronto: James Lorimer and Company Ltd; 2001.
5. The College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario Complaints Committee: Decision and Reasons. Claimant: Dr. Laurence Becker; respondent: Dr. Nancy Olivieri. Dec 19: No 44410. 2001.
6. Schafer A. Biomedical conflict of interest: a defence of the sequestration thesis – learning from the cases of Nancy Olivieri and David Healy. J Med Ethics 30(1):8-24.
7. Jenkins K. Re-thinking History. 1991. London: Routledge.
8. Oxford English Dictionary. 2003. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
The Introduction[1] to the very welcome Olivieri Symposium focuses on a “timeline of the most salient events”. Unfortunately, Viens and Savulescu left out several events of fundamental ethical concern and accepted some “facts” that are highly questionable. Most surprisingly, they have fallen into a common error: emphasising the scientific argument, when that is not their expertise, and bypassing the funda...
The Introduction[1] to the very welcome Olivieri Symposium focuses on a “timeline of the most salient events”. Unfortunately, Viens and Savulescu left out several events of fundamental ethical concern and accepted some “facts” that are highly questionable. Most surprisingly, they have fallen into a common error: emphasising the scientific argument, when that is not their expertise, and bypassing the fundamental ethical issue of the obligation to put concern for safety first. Thus their account both misleads in historical fact and misses the ethical point.
A critical omission:
The claimed objectivity of the Timeline is based on citation of three reports: Naimark[2], CAUT[3] and CPSO[4]. Inexplicably, the central conclusion of the Naimark report is not cited, while those of the later CAUT and CPSO reports are. Although all three reports address ethics, Naimark’s conclusions are strongly refuted by the CAUT and CPSO reports. Dr. Arnold Naimark was contracted by HSC to review the matter. Based on allegations by Dr. Hugh O’Brodovich, Paediatrician-in-Chief of the Hospital for Sick Children (HSC), his colleague Dr. Gideon Koren and Apotex Incorporated Vice-President Michael Spino[3], the Naimark report[2] alleged that Dr. Nancy Olivieri had failed to comply with ethical obligations in connection with her identification of unexpected risks of Apotex’s drug, deferiprone (L1). Throughout his investigation, Naimark’s appointment was the subject of controversy. As a result, a few weeks before the release of his report in December 1998, Dr. Naimark was joined by two of Canada’s leading ethicists, Drs. Frederick Lowy and Bartha Knoppers, who signed his report, upholding the allegations.
This central finding of the Naimark report was the basis of HSC’s strong actions against Dr. Olivieri during the next three years. It fueled the controversy from then onward, and the post-1998 story would be incomprehensible to a reader of JME who was unaware of it. Yet Drs. Viens and Savulescu failed to mention it.
The conclusions of the Naimark report were later found to be erroneous by the Canadian Association of University Teachers[3] and the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario[4]. The University of Toronto followed suit and all three fully exonerated Dr. Olivieri. In particular, the CPSO report found her ethical and clinical conduct “exemplary.” By omitting reference to the Naimark report’s now discredited findings, the Viens and Savulescu Timeline could mislead the reader into believing that this report can still reasonably be relied on.
Questionable “facts”: The CAUT report[3] determined that Dr. Koren had given false testimony against Dr. Olivieri to Dr. Naimark, and that he had worked closely with Drs. O’Brodovich and Spino in efforts to discredit her. The Naimark report[2] expressly relied on Dr. Koren’s testimony[3]. A year after the Naimark report was published, Dr. Koren was disciplined, publicly, by all three of the University of Toronto, HSC and CPSO[4] for persistent, extensive dishonesty, including “lying” in his attempts to discredit Dr. Olivieri. The most misleading passage from the Naimark report, cited uncritically in the Timeline, is the reference to two ‘letters’ provided by Dr. Koren to Dr. Naimark for his 1998 inquiry, bearing the ‘dates’ of “December 18, 1996” and “February 8, 1997”[3]. These two ‘letters’ have been discussed in three separate wider-ranging inquiries, each casting serious doubt on their authenticity and citing evidence that they were not written on the 1996 and 1997 ‘dates’ they bear, but instead in the fall of 1998. Dr. Olivieri never received either letter, and learned of them only after the Naimark report was published. Dr. Koren himself later acknowledged that he had destroyed evidence relevant to determining the actual dates on which the ‘letters’ were typed.
Still citing the Naimark report, the Timeline goes on to state, “Koren later publishes findings that L1 was effective and safe on a re-analysis of data.” In fact, as Dr. Koren subsequently acknowledged, these 1997 publications had been drafted by Apotex staff and he had agreed to be listed as senior author[3]. This was a year in which Dr. Koren held a $250,000 research grant from Apotex, but he did not disclose in these publications that he was funded by Apotex, nor did he disclose to the university the source or purpose of the grant[3].
Missing salient events: The Timeline does not mention that Dr. Koren was disciplined for professional misconduct by the CPSO (as well as by the hospital and the university)[5]. More surprisingly, it also omits that he was later disciplined again by the University for scientific misconduct in connection with a 1999 journal article favorable to deferiprone. His article did not disclose his Apotex financial support, did not cite earlier published findings of risks of the drug, did not report adverse data to which he had access, and did not acknowledge the work of Dr. Olivieri and the other scientists who had actually generated the data he used.
The Timeline does not mention that Apotex sent a whole series of legal warnings to Dr. Olivieri in efforts to deter her from disclosing risks to patients, other physicians and regulatory agencies. Apotex copied a number of these warning letters to the university, yet the university took no effective action to support Dr. Olivieri. The Timeline also omits that, simultaneously, the university and Apotex were in negotiations for a multimillion-dollar donation to enable the university to build a new biomedical science complex[3]. During these negotiations, the President Robert Prichard of the university wrote to the Prime Minister of Canada lobbying for patent regulations that would benefit Apotex.
Missing the ethical issue: The Introduction uses space for preliminary regulatory details and the biology of thalassemia and iron chelation, although the authors are not experts in either scientific field. Yet the fundamental ethical issue is missing. Dr. Olivieri identified a risk of lack of sustained efficacy and therefore possible harm, and insisted on informed patient consent and valid clinical trials to address the potential harms. Apotex prematurely terminated the trials and repeatedly tried to silence her with legal warnings. The fundamental ethical issue is the failure of Dr. Olivieri’s hospital and university to support her ethically correct approach to clinical science.
References
(1) Viens AM, Savulescu J. Introduction to The Olivieri symposium. J Med Ethics 2004;30(1):1-7.
(2) Naimark A, Knoppers B, Lowy F. Clinical trials of L1 (deferiprone) at The Hospital for Sick Children: a review of the facts and circumstances. Toronto: Hospital for Sick Children; 1998.
(3) Thompson J, Baird P, Downie J. Report of the Committee of Inquiry on the case involving Dr. Nancy Olivieri, the Hospital for Sick Children, the University of Toronto, and Apotex, Inc. Toronto: James Lorimer and Company Ltd; 2001.
(4) The College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario Complaints Committee: Decision and Reasons. Claimant: Dr. Laurence Becker; respondent: Dr. Nancy Olivieir. Dec 19: No 44410. 2001.
(5) Downie J, Baird P, Thompson J. Industry and the academy: conflicts of interest in contemporary health research. Health Law J 2002;10:103-22.
The paper by J Harris is well thought out and certainly
discusses one of the most difficult issues a doctor may
face; this includes not only breaking bad news but also
helping his/her patients with any ensuing decisions
regarding 'end of life decisions'.
As a paediatrician, one faces the additional difficulty
that one's patient is often unable to voice his/her wishes
or feelings. When faced with hav...
The paper by J Harris is well thought out and certainly
discusses one of the most difficult issues a doctor may
face; this includes not only breaking bad news but also
helping his/her patients with any ensuing decisions
regarding 'end of life decisions'.
As a paediatrician, one faces the additional difficulty
that one's patient is often unable to voice his/her wishes
or feelings. When faced with having to decide what to do
for their child ('to continue or not to'), parents are
often unable to come to a decision. Quite often during the
course of such lengthy discussions, one of the two parents
eventually asks: And what would you do, Doctor?
Up till now, that question remained a theoretical one for
myself. Being a parent now, this question would now carry
significantly more 'real' weight... How would I honestly
answer such a question??
I have read the recent theme issue on evidence based medicine and the
various articles have raised some disquiet, mainly because they seem to be
applying a concept of evidence based practice which assumes centralised
imposition of rules, rather than the generally accepted concept of seeking
and analysing the best evidence, using clinical judgment and adapting
these to the patients wishes,
I have read the recent theme issue on evidence based medicine and the
various articles have raised some disquiet, mainly because they seem to be
applying a concept of evidence based practice which assumes centralised
imposition of rules, rather than the generally accepted concept of seeking
and analysing the best evidence, using clinical judgment and adapting
these to the patients wishes,
Most authors appear to have made the assumption of medical
epistemology being an absolute form of knowledge, and attack EBP (Evidence
based practice) as providing imperfect knowledge, I was expecting a
variant of the ontological argument to emerge but thankfully the Cartesian
absolutism did not progress.
Medical diagnosis is similarly treated as an absolute – though we regard
ourselves as “knowing” a diagnosis it is not the meaning of the verb “to
know” as applied by the majority of your authors. “Knowing” to a medical
practitioner, is (or should be) a probabilistic assumption. “Knowing” a
diagnosis means we have matched in our memories a set of facts with what
we observe, or clinically judged to be present, it is a label for
classification and prognosticating it is not an absolute reality which
most of your authors seemed to have assumed. “Knowing” a treatment
similarly means we have matched a label (diagnosis) with past memories it
is similarly subject to weaknesses of our memory systems, and our
emotions. “Knowing” means that the assertion is highly probable not an
absolute.
While EBP has been hijacked by governments, government sponsored disease
lobby groups, and even the pharmaceutical industry and so called
guidelines produced it is inevitable that they will reflect the prejudices
and beliefs of the writer(s), and may reflect the extent of knowledge up
to the time the editor sends the final to the printer, that this may be
several years before the reader comes to apply it means that, though
evidence based, it is no longer current evidence. That this process has
occurred is irrelevant to the process of evidence based practice as the
principle of EBP means the practitioner will assess the guidelines as they
would any other set of information. A person considering the use of a
guideline should, as a first step see when it was published, and what
evidence is quoted. If there is no evidence base quoted throw the damn
thing away.
Another major concern was the expressed belief of some authors in the
immutability of knowledge. Though we have an agreed set of diagnostic
labels their application varies throughout world, we cannot even reach
consensus on the diagnosis of death (one of the epidemiologists binary
states) – our knowledge will always be imperfect and subjective. The
application of EBP (it is a process not a philosophy) aims to reduce the
subjectivity of externally acquired knowledge (i.e. what we do not observe
ourselves) because we recognise the imperfections of the system which
generates that knowledge. Poor experimental design, fraud, selective
publication, omission of key data to push a product, poor statistical
technique all act to mislead us when we are discussing options with our
patients and what the Cochrane collaboration, and meta analysis, and
systematic review do is hopefully weed out the misleading data. Of course
any systematic review will be subjective – we can reduce subjectivity( or
social values) not abolish it.
As individual practitioners our response to our patients and their
diagnoses becomes coloured by our experiences, we are animals we wish to
avoid pain both physical and emotional, one poor outcome may colour our
advice to the detriment of the patient – it is because of this we need a
source of up to date clinical evidence even though it will always be
imperfect and incomplete. In the past when medicine was less dynamic
textbooks sufficed as this source of evidence but reliance on textbooks in
our computerised society is decreasingly valid.
The application of EBP to quality improvement is also a process,
people who do not realise the realities of dealing with autonomous human
beings may assume that failing to prescribe what is suggested by current
evidence reflects poor practice – the only person who can make that
judgment is the practitioner – it is they who negotiates the treatment
plan, it is they to whom the patient expresses their fears beliefs and
prejudices and no one else can be party to that special arrangement. The
application of EBP in quality improvement is flagging deviation from
evidence and asking the practitioner to reflect on why they reached that
course of action.
Evidence based practice is a tool, just as a computer is a tool. Neither
represent a replacement of clinical judgment, or clinical skill and that
they are misused by the ignorant to try to alter our behaviour is not
valid grounds for rejection. Evidence based practice simply a further
change in the practice of medicine that our successors will master over
time, and some of us are trying to master now.
My apologies for the brevity of the arguments but this is merely a letter.
Dear Editor
I am pleased that the Journal of Medical Ethics has dealt with the ethics of circumcision. Circumcision has a seamy underside of violence and sexual abuse that can be seen in such disparate sources as the Bible [the hundred foreskin dowry] (1 Sam. 18:25-27) and the circumcision and slaughter of the Shechemites (Genesis chapter 34 ) [1]. A...
Dear editor
The case has been made for environmental influences, which might reasonably include medications taken as prescribed or consumed in contaminated water or food, having a profound effect upon future generations by influencing gamete selection [1].
In the case of obesity, for example, it was proposed that gametes might be evolutionarily selected to thrive on the diet to which they have access...
Dear Editor
Schaafsma and Verbeek are positive about the central ideas of our paper, as they endorse what we have named the intrusion and coordination model. They also regard the notion of coordination of worlds of norms and values that we develop in the last part, as appropriate for all medical disciplines and professions.
Their criticism, however, misses the point of the article. Far from undervaluing occ...
Dear Editor
I enjoyed the fable very much, and think that I am in agreement with much of the philosophical gloss. There is, however, one issue that troubles me. To kill the dragon of aging we need not only to develop life extension therapies, we need to develop immortality therapies. Otherwise there will still be trains going up the mountain, although for a given population size there will be fewer and fewer trains...
Dear Editor
We would like to comment on the recent theme issue on evidence based medicine, especially on the article about "Coordinating the norms and values of medical research, medical practice, and patient worlds." This is a title that appeals to all physicians with an interest in medical research and its implementation in medical practice. Vos et al. embark upon the important topic of evidence-based occupa...
Dear Editor
"Informed consent is a great advance towards protecting the rights and autonomy of patients.
However its usefulness is far from universal: informed consent cannot clarify the secondary use of tissues, as the authors point out, and in practice its use is more and more a manner of legal protection against malpractice claims in various countries, and a virtual nonentity in emergency situations,
...Dear Editor
I want to thank Dr Olivieri’s core set of long-standing supporters for their letter [1] on the Introduction to the Olivieri Symposium that was recently published in the Journal of Medical Ethics.[2] Gallie et al. have been staunch supporters of Dr. Olivieri for years, and this support on her behalf has played a pivotal role in attempting to clarify perceived mistakes made in public and academic repo...
Dear editor,
The Introduction[1] to the very welcome Olivieri Symposium focuses on a “timeline of the most salient events”. Unfortunately, Viens and Savulescu left out several events of fundamental ethical concern and accepted some “facts” that are highly questionable. Most surprisingly, they have fallen into a common error: emphasising the scientific argument, when that is not their expertise, and bypassing the funda...
Dear Editor
The paper by J Harris is well thought out and certainly discusses one of the most difficult issues a doctor may face; this includes not only breaking bad news but also helping his/her patients with any ensuing decisions regarding 'end of life decisions'. As a paediatrician, one faces the additional difficulty that one's patient is often unable to voice his/her wishes or feelings. When faced with hav...
Dear Editor
I have read the recent theme issue on evidence based medicine and the various articles have raised some disquiet, mainly because they seem to be applying a concept of evidence based practice which assumes centralised imposition of rules, rather than the generally accepted concept of seeking and analysing the best evidence, using clinical judgment and adapting these to the patients wishes,
Most...
Pages