Article Text
Abstract
We read with interest the extended essay published from Riisfeldt and are encouraged by an empirical ethics article which attempts to ground theory and its claims in the real world. However, such attempts also have real-world consequences. We are concerned to read the paper’s conclusion that clinical evidence weakens the distinction between euthanasia and normal palliative care prescribing. This is important. Globally, the most significant barrier to adequate symptom control in people with life-limiting illness is poor access to opioid analgesia. Opiophobia makes clinicians reluctant to prescribe and their patients reluctant to take opioids that might provide significant improvements in quality of life. We argue that the evidence base for the safety of opioid prescribing is broader than that presented, restricting the search to palliative care literature produces significant bias as safety experience and literature for opioids and sedatives exists in many fields. This is not acknowledged in the synthesis presented. By considering additional evidence, we reject the need for agnosticism and reaffirm that palliative opioid prescribing is safe. Second, palliative sedation in a clinical context is a poorly defined concept covering multiple interventions and treatment intentions. We detail these and show that continuous deep palliative sedation (CDPS) is a specific practice that remains controversial globally and is not considered routine practice. Rejecting agnosticism towards opioids and excluding CDPS from the definition of routine care allows the rejection of Riisfeldt’s headline conclusion. On these grounds, we reaffirm the important distinction between palliative care prescribing and euthanasia in practice.
- palliative care
- euthanasia
- end-of-life
- clinical ethics
Statistics from Altmetric.com
Footnotes
Contributors All authors conceived the response. GS, CG and RG wrote the first draft of the manuscript. All authors contributed to subsequent drafting and critical revisions. All authors approved the final version.
Funding GS is supported by Wellcome Trust Research Award for Health Professionals (208129/Z/17/Z).
Competing interests None declared.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
Data sharing statement This is a response article and contains no data.
Patient consent for publication Not required.
Linked Articles
- Extended essay
- Response
- Response
Read the full text or download the PDF:
Other content recommended for you
- A response to critics: weakening the ethical distinction between euthanasia, palliative opioid use and palliative sedation
- Terminal sedation and the “imminence condition”
- Weakening the ethical distinction between euthanasia, palliative opioid use and palliative sedation
- Approaches to suffering at the end of life: the use of sedation in the USA and Netherlands
- Euthanasia and palliative sedation in Belgium
- Ethical end-of-life palliative care: response to Riisfeldt
- Strengthening the ethical distinction between euthanasia, palliative opioid use and palliative sedation
- Moral differences in deep continuous palliative sedation and euthanasia
- Palliative sedation determinants: systematic review and meta-analysis in palliative medicine
- Expanded terminal sedation in end-of-life care