Article Text
Statistics from Altmetric.com
- Applied and Professional Ethics
- Cultural Pluralism
- Religious Ethics
- Moral and Religious Aspects
- Philosophical Ethics
‘Why religion deserves a place in ‘secular’ medicine’1 has provoked three commentaries—one each from Kevin R Smith, Brian D Earp and Xavier Symons. I am grateful to all of these for taking the time and trouble. In the response that follows the constraints of space have precluded me from being comprehensive and required me to be terse.
Kevin Smith objects to my argument in favour of religion's place at the ‘secular’ table of deliberation about medical ethics on the following grounds: religious ethics are not universal, many of their claims appeal to God's authority rather than to reason, they fail to take into account the possibilities that modern technology offers, when they are rational they cease to be religious, and it is incapable of the give-and-take of rational exchange. In contrast, Smith tells us, ‘secular’ ethics in general are based on a set of principles that are open to rational analysis, and utilitarianism in particular has the potential to attract universal agreement ‘because happiness and suffering … are respectively high valued and strongly deprecated by virtually all agents’.
Smith seems unaware of how controversial his narrow concept of reason is, adopts a simplistic understanding of the relationship between reason and authority, fails to distinguish between popular religion and the academic discipline of religious ethics, writes unfairly about contemporary developments in the latter, neglects to acknowledge the strength of opposition within moral philosophy to utilitarianism, and entertains a utopian view of the possibility of universal ethical consensus. On the other hand, the issue he raises about the relationship between the nature of the religious ethicist's ethical reasons and their relationship to his religious convictions is a crucial one, and it deserves more clarity than I gave it in my article. I shall address this later, but first let me make …
Footnotes
Competing interests None declared.
Provenance and peer review Commissioned; internally peer reviewed.
Request Permissions
If you wish to reuse any or all of this article please use the link below which will take you to the Copyright Clearance Center’s RightsLink service. You will be able to get a quick price and instant permission to reuse the content in many different ways.
Copyright information:
Linked Articles
- Clinical ethics
- Commentary
- The concise argument
- Reproductive ethics
- Commentary
- Commentary
Read the full text or download the PDF:
Other content recommended for you
- On the univocity of rationality: a response to Nigel Biggar ’s ‘ Why religion deserves a place in secular medicine ’
- Doing good medical ethics: a Christian perspective
- Religion, secular medicine and utilitarianism: a response to Biggar
- Why religion deserves a place in secular medicine
- Further clarity on cooperation and morality
- The religious beliefs of students and the teaching of medical ethics: a comment on Brassington
- Some principles of Islamic ethics as found in Harrisian philosophy
- Does religion deserve a place in secular medicine
- Death - whose decision? Euthanasia and the terminally ill
- Early European attitudes towards “ good death ”: Eugenios Voulgaris, Treatise on euthanasia, St Petersburg, 1804