Article Text
Abstract
A number of prominent bioethicists, such as Parker, Lucassen and Knoppers, have called for the adoption of a system in which by default genetic information is shared among family members. This paper suggests that a main reason given in support of this call to share genetic information among family members is the idea that genetic information is essentially familial in nature. On examining this “familial nature of genetics” argument, the paper shows that most genetic information is only shared in a weaker way among family members and does not necessarily lead to the actual manifestation of particular diseases. The upshot is that the idea that genetic information is familial in nature does not provide sufficient ground for moving towards a system in which by default genetic information is shared among family members.
Statistics from Altmetric.com
THE FAMILIAL NATURE OF GENETIC INFORMATION
As predictive genetic testing becomes prevalent, the following kinds of cases will arise more and more frequently in clinical genetic settings:
Case 1 (Anna, Betty and Carl): Anna and Betty are sisters who do not get along and rarely speak to one another. Anna has just learned that her 2-year-old son, Carl, has Duchenne muscular dystrophy. Betty has recently married and is planning parenthood. Anna knows that Betty would consider preimplantation genetic diagnosis or not have children at all if Betty knew about Carl’s condition. The genetic staff offered Anna to help communicate Carl’s diagnosis to Betty so that Betty can make an informed decision about her reproductive choices. However, Anna declines this offer, reasoning that Betty should be personally responsible for her own health and reproductive conditions.
Case 2 (Fred, Garry and Heather): on his fifty-fifth birthday, Fred was diagnosed with Huntington disease. Fred informs the medical staff that he does not want his son, Garry, to know about this diagnosis, believing that Garry will blame him for bearing faulty genes. Garry himself has explicitly said that he does not want to know about any predisposition to any genetic disease. His wife, Heather, is however 9 weeks pregnant and would consider an abortion if the fetus were found to have the Huntington disease gene mutation.
These cases raise at least the following ethical questions: Does Anna have a duty to disclose to Betty that Carl has Duchenne muscular dystrophy? Do the medical staff have a duty to inform Heather that her father-in-law has Huntington disease?
Although some governmental bodies have argued that a confidentiality agreement with a patient should be paramount,1 other government bodies have said that it may sometimes be justified to disclose genetic information to other family members, even if an individual desires confidentiality. For example, the UK General Medical Council guidelines on confidentiality, which are not specifically aimed at genetics, but which are the main guidelines to which practitioners in genetics would be accountable, state that confidentiality “may” be breached when there is “risk of death or serious harm”.2 3 Similarly, the American Society of Human Genetics Social Issues Subcommittee on Familial Disclosure permits professionals to breach confidentiality in exceptional cases.4
Some prominent bioethicists have gone further and argued that, by default, genetic information should be shared among family members. For example, Parker and Lucassen proposed that in the case of genetic information, we should seriously consider moving away from a “personal account model” towards a “joint account model”.5 As Parker and Lucassen5 explain:
“Whereas on the personal account model the default position is an assumption of confidentiality, on the joint account model it is assumed that information should be available to all account holders unless there are good reasons to do otherwise.”
Other bioethicists have made similar claims.6 7
A main reason given in support of this call to share genetic information among family members is the idea that genetic information is essentially familial in nature. Call this the “genetic information is familial thesis” (GIFT). For example, Parker and Lucassen5 write, “Genetic information is, spontaneous mutations aside, essentially and unavoidably familial in nature.” Or Knoppers6 says that:
“the very nature of genetic information, as both individual and universal, now mandates its treatment as familial.”
On the surface, GIFT seems like a very plausible thesis. Certainly, those who believe in “genetic exceptionalism”, according to which genetic information is unique in medicine and deserves special treatment, also typically point to GIFT in order to support genetic exceptionalism. For instance, Roche and Annas8 cite the fact that “an individual’s DNA can also reveal information about risks and traits that are shared with genetic relatives” as a reason for holding onto the view that separate rules and laws are needed for handling genetic information. Also, even those who have argued against genetic exceptionalism seem to accept GIFT. For example, with respect to the point that genetic information is familial in nature, Murray’s9 response is to accept it but to note that other kinds of medical information such as one’s cholesterol level or whether one has been exposed to an infectious disease are also familial in nature. Given that GIFT appears to be widely accepted, basing the call to share genetic information among family members on GIFT seems to have certain initial plausibility.
However, I shall argue that GIFT requires refinement, and that once refined, one sees that most genetic information is only shared in a weak way among family members and does not necessarily lead to the actual manifestation of particular diseases. The upshot is that GIFT does not provide sufficient ground for moving towards a system in which by default genetic information is shared among family members. It is worth saying at the outset that I am not making the stronger claim that there can be no valid reason why we should adopt a system in which by default genetic information is shared among family members. There may be other ways of grounding the duty to share our genetic information with family members. In this paper, I am only making the weaker claim that GIFT does not furnish such a reason.
REFINING GIFT
Without refinement, the impression one gets from the idea that genetic information is familial in nature—that is, GIFT, is that there is a very high correlation between knowing that an individual has the genes for a particular genetic disease and being justified in believing/inferring that a relative will also have this particular disease. But GIFT requires refinement in the following ways.
First, when Parker and Lucassen say that genetic information is spontaneous mutations aside essentially familial in nature, this statement makes spontaneous mutations seem as if they occur infrequently. However, depending on the genetic disease at issue, spontaneous mutations can in fact occur frequently. For example, in the case of Duchenne muscular dystrophy, one in three cases is the result of spontaneous mutation.10 This means that the probability that this disease is “familial in nature” is only two-thirds or 66%.
Second, it is helpful to distinguish between different kinds of genetic relations; some are stronger and some are weaker:
Stronger genetic relation: if two individuals X and Y are biologically related in a certain way, and if all you know is that X has genes G then you are justified in believing to a high degree of probability (P) that Y also has G;
Weaker genetic relation: if two individuals X and Y are biologically related in a certain way, and if all you know is that X has genes G then you are justified in believing to a medium-to-low degree of probability (P) that Y also has G. (Note that I shall use actual probabilities later on.)
An example of a stronger genetic relation is the case of monozygotic twins. Suppose Adam and Bob are monozygotic twins, and suppose all you know is that Adam has genes for Huntington disease. As monozygotic twins typically have identical genetic make-up, you are justified in believing that there is a high degree of probability that Bob also has the genes for Huntington disease. An example of a weaker genetic relation is the case of a mother and her son. Suppose all you know is that Clara, a mother, has genes for Huntington disease. Then, given that typically an offspring gets only half of his or her genes from the mother, you are justified in believing that there is a medium-to-low degree of probability that David, Clara’s biological son, also has the genes for Huntington disease. It should be obvious that stronger genetic relations occur only in a handful of cases. In addition to monozygotic twins, if human cloning became possible and was practised, then there would also be stronger genetic relations in those cases. Other than that, most genetic relations would be weaker genetic relations.
Third, and finally, some genes are highly penetrant while others are not, where penetrance is the proportion of individuals’ carrying a particular variation of a gene that also expresses a particular trait—for example, a particular disease. Let us call cases in which individuals have highly penetrant genes “deterministic”, and cases in which individuals have low penetrant genes “non-deterministic”.
Deterministic case: if all you know is that an individual X has the genes for a disease, you are justified in believing to a high degree of probability (Q) that X will develop the disease.
Non-deterministic case: if all you know is that an individual X has the genes for a disease, you are justified in believing to a medium-to-low degree of probability (Q) that X will develop the disease.
An example of a deterministic case may be someone, for instance Paul, who has the genes for Huntington disease. Given that Huntington disease has a 95% penetrance, whereby 95% of those with the dominant allele for Huntington disease develop the disease and 5% do not, you may be justified in believing to a high degree of probability that Paul will develop Huntington disease. An example of a non-deterministic case may be someone, for instance Peach, who has a BRCA1 mutation. Given the medium-to-low penetrance of BRCA1 for breast cancer (the penetrance of BRCA1 is about 49.9% (27.5% to 72.3%)11 for someone with moderate risk—that is, someone with one first-degree relative or two second-degree relatives on the same side of the family with breast or ovarian cancer), you may be justified in believing to a medium-to-low degree of probability that Peach will develop breast cancer.
For our purpose, deterministic cases are the exceptions rather than the norm. With a few relatively rare disorders such as Tay–Sachs, Huntington disease, phenylketonuria, Duchene muscular dystrophy, cystic fibrosis, and so on, a single gene alternation does not in itself predict disease. In fact, even in these single gene disorders, gene–environment and gene–gene interactions can still influence whether a disease will be expressed.12
APPLYING REFINED GIFT
To see how these refinements affect the debate regarding whether a patient’s confidentiality should be paramount or whether genetic information should be shared by default with family members, let us first generalise the discussions above.
As a start, consider the likelihood that a particular genetic disease is the result of a spontaneous mutation. If the genetic disease is not due to spontaneous mutation, we can next identify at least four variants of the thesis that genetic information is familial by combining the stronger and weaker genetic relations with deterministic and non-deterministic cases.
Stronger deterministic GIFT: if two individuals X and Y are biologically related in a certain way, and if all you know is that X has a disease as a result of having certain genes, you are justified in believing to a high degree of probability (high P × high Q) that Y will develop the disease. (Recall that P is the degree of probability that one individual will have certain genes, if another individual has them; and Q is the degree of probability that an individual will develop a particular disease if the individual has certain genes).
Stronger non-deterministic GIFT: if two individuals X and Y are biologically related in a certain way, and if all you know is that X has a disease as a result of having certain genes, you are justified in believing to a medium degree of probability (high P × medium-to-low Q) that Y will also develop the disease.
Weaker deterministic GIFT: if two individuals X and Y are biologically related in a certain way, and if all you know is that X has a disease as a result of having certain genes, then you are justified in believing to a medium degree of probability (medium-to-low P × high Q) that Y will also develop the disease.
Weaker non-deterministic GIFT: if two individuals X and Y are biologically related in a certain way, and if all you know is that X has a disease as a result of having certain genes, then you are justified in believing to a medium-to-low degree of probability (medium-to-low P × medium-to-low Q) that Y will also develop the disease.
As can be seen, the pressure to share genetic information with other family members is the strongest when stronger deterministic GIFT is operative. For example, on the one hand, if by virtue of knowing that John has a certain disease as a result of having certain genes you are justified in believing to a high degree of probability that Jack will also have the same disease, it seems that you would have a stronger obligation to let Jack know about this risk. On the other hand, if weaker versions of GIFT are operative, then the pressure to share genetic information with other family members will be lower. For example, if in virtue of knowing that Paula has a certain disease as a result of having certain genes you are only justified in believing to a medium-to-low degree of probability that Pamela will also have the same disease, it seems that you would have a weaker obligation to let Pamela know about this risk.
Lest it lead to misunderstanding, let me note that a medium-to-low degree of probability that an individual will have a particular disease does not thereby mean that this is only a medium-to-low level of moral significance. A medium-to-low degree of probability that an individual will have a particular disease may still be quite a morally significant matter. As I shall shortly discuss, the crucial issue for us is whether such a level of probability is sufficient to override confidentiality.
As mentioned above, clearly in most clinical cases some weaker versions of GIFT are operative. This means that in most cases, there will be less pressure to share genetic information with other family members. To illustrate this, lets consider again the cases at the outset, which are representative of the kinds of cases that clinicians are likely to face in clinical genetic settings.13 Owing to space, I shall describe case 1 in more detail, and summarise the finding of case 2.
Case 1 (Anna, Betty and Carl): recall that Anna has a 2-year-old son, Carl, who has Duchenne muscular dystrophy, and we are trying to decide whether Anna has a duty to inform her sister Betty who is thinking about having a child of her own. Duchenne muscular dystrophy is one of the more penetrant genetic diseases. So this case falls under weaker deterministic GIFT. Based on the previous discussions, we should consider how likely it is that if Betty had a son (if Betty had a daughter, the daughter would only be a carrier and would not manifest this disease), he will have Duchenne muscular dystrophy by taking into account the following:
As mentioned above, one in three cases of Duchenne muscular dystrophy is a de novo mutation. So there is only a two-thirds chance that Carl inherited this disease from one of his parents.
To keep things simple, we can assume that Anna’s husband does not have this disease, because symptoms for this disease usually appear in childhood. So if the husband had this disease, presumably Anna’s sister Betty would have learned about this at some point.
If Anna was a carrier, it is also possible that she acquired this disease through a spontaneous mutation. So, there is only a two-thirds chance that Anna inherited this disease from one of her parents.
If one of Anna’s and Betty’s parents was a carrier (we can assume that it is the mother for the same reason we assumed that Anna is the carrier), there is only a one in two chance that Betty is also a carrier.
Finally, Duchenne muscular dystrophy is an X-linked recessive disease. So, should Betty become pregnant, there is only a one in four chance that she would have a son who will develop this disease.
So a rough estimate of the probability that Betty will have a son who will develop this disease given that Carl has it is:
2/3 (Anna’s son inherited this disease from Anna) × 2/3 (Anna inherited this disease from her mother) × 1/2 (Betty is a carrier) × 1/4 (Betty will have a son with this disease) = 1/18 or 5.5%.
Case 2 (Fred, Garry and Heather): using similar reasoning, a rough estimate of the probability that Heather’s offspring will have the Huntington disease is:
1/2 (Garry has inherited this disease from his father) × 1/2 (Heather’s offspring has inherited this disease from Garry) × 95/100 (penetrance of Huntington disease) = 19/80 or 24%.
A CASE AGAINST SHARING GENETIC INFORMATION
What can we learn from the analysis above? Admittedly, 24%, which is the higher probability of the two cases, is not an insignificant figure. But this is still a lot lower than the unrefined GIFT which gives the impression of a very high correlation between knowing that an individual has the genes for a particular genetic disease and being justified in believing/inferring that a relative will also have this particular disease. Also, given that de novo mutations of Huntington’s disease are rare, it is likely that in this case there already exists a known family history of this disease. If so, this could possibly render moot the issue of whether one should share genetic information with other family members in such a case. In addition, the probability of harm in some cases of weaker deterministic GIFT can be as low as 5.5%, as for example in Anna, Betty and Carl’s case.
Moreover, it is worth mentioning that the kinds of harm at issue are not ones of causing harm, but rather ones of allowing harm to take place. We can all agree that with respect to causing harm, the threshold of risk of harm should be very low. Indeed, if an action of mine has even a small chance of causing you harm, then certainly I should take steps to refrain from taking such an action; or, if such an action were unavoidable, then certainly I am obligated to inform you of it. But, arguably, the situation is not symmetrical with respect to allowing harm. Indeed, those government bodies that allow confidentiality to be over-ridden, permit this only in “exceptional circumstances”, namely, if there is a risk of death or serious harm to a third party. In the USA, the Tarasoff case has been used as a precedent for a clinician’s duty to warn in cases of immediate and serious threat.14
In fact, in non-genetic settings with comparable levels of risk and in which an individual is not just allowing harm but could also cause harm, clinicians and government bodies have not tried to establish a duty to warn family members. For example, clinicians have not been required to inform family members that one of their family members is an alcoholic and may endanger them—for example, by setting their house on fire. Nor have clinicians been required to acquire the names of sexual partners to whom an individual may have transmitted a chlamydia infection so that they can warn these individuals of the danger to their partners.
Be that as it may, for this purpose, is a 5.5% or even a 24% risk of harm serious, imminent and likely? It does not seem so. It is hard to see how these probabilities constitute “imminent” threats. Given that most clinical cases will be like these cases, in that some weaker versions of GIFT will be operative, and given that the probabilities in most of these weaker versions of GIFT are not imminent, it seems that most of these cases would not be exceptional enough to over-ride a patient’s confidentiality. If this is right, the idea that genetic information is familial in nature does not seem to provide sufficient ground for why we should move towards a system in which by default we would share our genetic information with our relatives.
Acknowledgments
I thank J Savulescu, M Parker, D Wilkinson, W Gruetjen and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.
Footnotes
Competing interests: None.
Provenance and peer review: not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
Linked Articles
Other content recommended for you
- Familial genetic risks: how can we better navigate patient confidentiality and appropriate risk disclosure to relatives?
- Genetic discrimination in life insurance: empirical evidence from a cross sectional survey of genetic support groups in the United Kingdom
- From proband to provider: is there an obligation to inform genetic relatives of actionable risks discovered through direct-to-consumer genetic testing?
- The routinisation of genomics and genetics: implications for ethical practices
- Disclosure ‘downunder’: misadventures in Australian genetic privacy law
- Attitudes of healthcare professionals and parents regarding genetic testing for violent traits in childhood
- The new genetics: Genetic testing and public policy
- Genetic information: a joint account?
- The right not to know and preimplantation genetic diagnosis for Huntington’s disease
- Rights and duties of genetic counsellors in Germany related to relatives at risk: comparative thoughts on the German Genetic Diagnostics Act