Article Text

Download PDFPDF

Is conceiving a child to benefit another against the interests of the new child?
Free
  1. M Spriggs
  1. Correspondence to:
 M Spriggs
 Ethics Unit, Murdoch Children’s Research Institute, Royal Children’s Hospital, Flemington Road, Parkville, Victoria, 3052; University of Melbourne, Centre for Human Bioethics, Monash University, Australia; spriggsmmurdoch.rch.unimelb.edu.au

Abstract

Conceiving a child by way of embryo selection and tissue matching to benefit a sick sibling is generally justified on the grounds that as well as the potential to save the sick child, there is a benefit for the new baby. The new baby is selected so he or she will not have the disease suffered by the first child. It is not possible, however, to select against conditions for which there is no test and Jamie Whitaker’s birth is a case where the process of in vitro fertilisation with tissue matching is viewed as being of benefit only to a third party—the sick child. Some people object to using the technology for this purpose. There are also good reasons to argue that the technology should be used to save a sick child, and that it would be morally remiss for Jamie’s parents not to consent to the use of his cord blood.

  • designer baby
  • saviour sibling
  • IVF
  • HFEA

Statistics from Altmetric.com

Request Permissions

If you wish to reuse any or all of this article please use the link below which will take you to the Copyright Clearance Center’s RightsLink service. You will be able to get a quick price and instant permission to reuse the content in many different ways.

Saviour siblings are not harmed

An application of in vitro fertilisation (IVF) allows parents to select an embryo free from serious genetic disease and simultaneously select for a tissue match so that the umbilical cord blood of the resulting baby can provide stem cells to treat a seriously ill sibling. The procedure which involves preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) together with tissue typing has been carried out successfully in the USA, where private fertility clinics are unregulated, and has been approved in Australia and the UK.1–4 The procedure is generally justified on the grounds that it benefits the new baby by selecting against a hereditary disease.

REQUEST FOR PGD AND TISSUE MATCHING REFUSED

In August 2002, the UK’s Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA) refused a request for PGD and tissue matching by Michelle and Jayson Whitaker, the parents of Charlie, a child suffering from Diamond–Blackfan anaemia.5 The request was refused because the HFEA will only allow a cell to be tissue typed if it has been taken to test for illness. As there is no genetic test for Diamond–Blackfan anaemia, “it could not be argued that PGD was necessary to select embryos free from the condition”.5,6 Charlie, the Whitaker’s existing child, but not the new baby, would benefit from the procedure.7

Diamond–Blackfan anaemia is a rare condition that requires painful treatment. Charlie requires blood transfusions and painful daily injections to keep him alive. The only cure is a transplant of stem cells that are a perfect tissue match.7 The Whitakers had a one in four chance of naturally conceiving a child who would be a match for their sick child but that could be increased to around 98% with PGD and tissue typing.8

JAMIE WHITAKER, A PERFECT MATCH SIBLING, IS BORN

After the HFEA refused the procedure, the Whitakers sought treatment in the USA at the Reproductive Genetics Institute in Chicago, Illinois. Michelle Whitaker has now given birth to a baby named Jamie, who was genetically matched to their existing child, Charlie.4 Tests have shown that the baby is a perfect match but further tests are needed to see if he is free of the disease.9 There is a small chance, a one in fifty chance, that Jamie may have the disease. The Whitakers must wait six months to know for sure.10

“DESIGNER BABY” DEBATE RE-IGNITED

The birth of Jamie has re-ignited debate about babies created to help their sick siblings. According to the father of Charlie and Jamie: “All we did was change the odds from a one-in-four chance of a tissue match to a 98% chance”.4 The British Medical Association has “applauded” the Whitakers’ actions7:

As doctors we believe that where technology exists that could help a dying or seriously ill child, without involving major risks for others, then it can only be right that it is used for this purpose.The welfare of the child born as a result of the treatment is of crucial importance. But in our view this is not incompatible with allowing selection of embryos on the basis of tissue type.

Jayson Whitaker’s comments give weight to the BMA’s view; that allowing PGD with tissue typing is not incompatible with the welfare of the child created. After Jamie’s birth, he said, “There are blood tests being carried out now to see if Jamie is a perfect tissue match and we will know in a few days, but at the moment we don’t want to think about the stem cell blood.” He also said: “The night before [Jamie] was born I didn’t even care about the cord blood. I just kept thinking, ‘I hope he’s all right.’”11

Opponents of the technology argue in terms of dignity and the idea that using the new child for the benefit of another is morally objectionable. According to John Smeaton, director of the Society for the Protection of Unborn Children3:

While our hearts go out to everybody involved, and we welcome Jamie Whitaker’s birth, there are profound issues of concern here … Human beings who were not the perfect match were simply discarded and a child has been created with the primary purpose of benefiting this elder brother. This does not conform to Jamie’s human dignity.

Britain’s fertility pioneer Lord Winston opposes the treatment and asks: “Can you think of any other medical treatment which you would expect anybody to undergo without informed consent for somebody else’s benefit?” He also raises concerns about the position of a child such as Jamie Whitaker: “This child has the spectre of being born for somebody else’s benefit throughout his whole life.”7

It is worth looking at arguments opposing the creation of Jamie Whitaker more closely to see if they reveal something not compatible with his welfare or whether some moral principle has been transgressed.

HUMAN DIGNITY

First of all, it is not clear how Jamie’s “human dignity” has been or will be compromised or why his dignity is of such magnitude that it is more important than his brother’s life. We have to wonder what this notion of dignity consists of and whether it is something that should be protected at all costs. It might be thought that Jamie is harmed if his dignity is violated or compromised and the moral significance of the harm hinges on the fact that Jamie was created to make some kind of sacrifice—that in resorting to PGD and tissue typing, the Whitakers have taken something from Jamie or compromised him in some way. And the thing that is missing or compromised is his human dignity. As we can see, there is a kind of circularity in arguments which defend human dignity and it is not clear why the protection of this vague notion, the value of which seems unable to be clearly articulated, should trump the life (and presumably the dignity) of another child. Appeals to human dignity tend to be based in religion—not in reasoned argument.

We might think that those who are concerned about Jamie’s human dignity would support therapeutic cloning if that could provide the stem cells Charlie needs. The Whitakers would not need to create an extra child—although if they wanted another child they could still have another child and without being criticised for compromising the child’s human dignity. Nevertheless, recommending therapeutic cloning is unlikely to appease all critics of PGD and tissue typing. Concerns about human dignity are likely to resurface in relation to the destruction of embryos in the cloning process. In other words, appeals to human dignity reduce to an argument for the moral standing of embryos. Appeals to human dignity are very often religious views in disguise.12

LACK OF CONSENT

Lord Winston’s concern about lack of consent distracts us from more important issues. The lack of consent is not morally significant in this case. Newborn babies are simply not equipped to give consent. Jamie’s parents have the authority to make decisions for Jamie and for his cord blood. Unless donating Jamie’s cord blood is not consistent with his welfare there is no reason to challenge their decision.13 Taking stem cells from the umbilical cord poses no risk and no inconvenience to the new baby. Nevertheless, some people might think it morally problematic that the intervention is for the sake of a third party and they might think Jamie’s parents have a conflict of interest. Generally we don’t allow medical interventions to be carried out on one person for the sake of another but when we think of medical interventions we usually think of procedures that are invasive and risky, or at the very least inconvenient. But that is not the case here. Not even a hair on the head of the new baby has been touched. Lord Winston’s question about comparable situations, about undergoing treatment for someone else’s benefit without informed consent, is easy to answer. If comparable situations exist, they should proceed—even without informed consent. A comparable situation might be—using a stored tissue sample to assist someone suffering from a life-threatening condition.

CONCLUSION

The interesting thing about this case is that it demonstrates that there is more than one kind of situation in which a parent’s consent on behalf of their child is justified. Consent is sometimes considered valid only when the intervention consented to “serves the best interests of the child” but there is another situation where consent is within acceptable limits. Another standard is consent to an intervention that is “not against the interests of the child”.14 Parental consent for some non-therapeutic research on children fits this category—for example, allowing extra blood to be taken during diagnostic or treatment procedures for “legitimate research purposes” involving no additional risk or discomfort.15 In a situation that requires an intervention involving no sacrifice and no inconvenience by one child to save the life of another child, parental consent is morally acceptable. It may even be morally required.

Saviour siblings are not harmed

REFERENCES