Article Text
Statistics from Altmetric.com
Could it ever be ethically justifiable to remove a dead man’s sperm to enable his partner to bear a child to him? If he had clearly indicated his agreement to this in advance, then the posthumous removal of his sperm for this purpose can be ethically justified, particularly in circumstances where the interests of the resulting child can be adequately met. Few dead men would have addressed such a possibility while alive, however, unless they had a specific reason to consider such an issue, perhaps because of a terminal illness. Without a prior indication that removal of his sperm for this purpose would be in accordance with his wishes in such circumstances, the posthumous use of a man’s sperm for procreation is unethical.
Posthumously removing organs and tissue from those who have given prior consent to this is commonly thought ethically acceptable. Indeed, some argue that cadaveric organ donation can be ethically justifiable in the absence of an explicit prior directive from the donor, so long as there is reason to believe this to be consistent with the values of the deceased person. Whatever we make of this latter suggestion, however, it does not follow that cadaveric sperm donation is justifiable in similar circumstances.
Deciding on behalf of another (on the basis of their known values) that their organs and tissue will be donated to other patients is one thing, but deciding on behalf of another that they will have offspring raises some significantly different issues. (Of course, some men might regard donating their sperm as akin to the posthumous donation of an unneeded organ, but many men do not view sperm donation in that way.) Indeed, those same values—for example, of personal intimacy—that help justify women’s reproductive decisions (regarding access to assisted reproductive technologies and abortion) as being within a protected zone relatively free of state intervention are the values which, for many men, would make being volunteered by another—even one’s surviving partner—to have offspring a deeply intrusive practice.†
Although procreation may be a fundamental human interest, plenty of fertile people autonomously choose to forgo altogether having children. Someone who thinks, for example, that he would be unable because of other commitments to help raise a child, might believe that his absences would be sufficiently detrimental to any prospective child that he would autonomously choose not to become a parent (even if his partner was willing to carry a disproportionate share of the parenting burdens). If a clinically dead man had such a view, but had not documented in writing that his sperm was not to be posthumously harvested for reproduction, would it really be justifiable for his surviving partner to harvest his sperm? It does not follow from the fact that a person, while alive, was very keen to have children with his partner that he would have wished his partner to conceive and bear a child to him after his death.
As Spriggs points out, prior to his accidental death in North Queensland, Andrew Clough had expressed a keen desire to have children with his partner Simone Baker. He may also have been a sperm donor in earlier years, and he had given consent for his organs to be donated in the event of his death. Nevertheless, it should not be inferred from these observations that Andrew would have wanted his sperm used by Simone to conceive and bear a child after his death. It is perfectly consistent to want children with one’s partner while one is alive, but to prefer that one is not posthumously made a parent after one’s death. There can be good reasons for preferring not to become a posthumous parent. As his death was unanticipated, it seems that Andrew did not have occasion to address such a contingency with his partner Simone. Without Andrew’s prior authorisation for his sperm to be used for procreation after his death, I believe that the posthumous removal of his sperm for this purpose cannot be ethically justified.
Footnotes
-
↵† Justice Blackman famously argued, in delivering the opinion of the US Supreme Court in the landmark abortion case of Roe v Wade (1973), that “the Court has recognized that a right of personal privacy, or a guarantee of personal privacy, does exist under the Constitution” and that a line of Supreme Court decisions “make it clear that only personal rights that can be deemed ‘fundamental’…are included in this guarantee of personal privacy. They also make it clear that the right has some extension to activities relating to marriage…procreation…contraception…family relationships…and child rearing and education”.
Other content recommended for you
- The ethical case for non-directed postmortem sperm donation
- Who owns a dead man’s sperm?
- Is posthumous semen retrieval ethically permissible?
- How medical ethical principles are applied in treatment with artificial insemination by donors (AID) in Hunan, China: effective practice at the Reproductive and Genetic Hospital of CITIC-Xiangya
- Woman wants dead fiancé’s baby: who owns a dead man’s sperm
- Response to Orr and Siegler—collective intentionality and procreative desires: the permissible view on consent to posthumous conception
- Postmortem non-directed sperm donation: quality matters
- Parent-initiated posthumous-assisted reproduction revisited in light of the interest in genetic origins
- Maps of beauty and disease: thoughts on genetics, confidentiality, and biological family
- Differences between sperm sharing and egg sharing are morally relevant