Distinguishing research from clinical care in cancer genetics: Theoretical justifications and practical strategies

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socscimed.2009.03.010Get rights and content

Abstract

The relationship between clinical research and clinical care is often perceived as unclear, particularly in highly technological subspecialties. This ambiguity is illustrated in cancer genetics where research protocols are frequently used to provide access to procedures that may be offered as a clinical service in other specialties. The project on which this paper is based investigated lay and expert perceptions of the activities which take place within the cancer genetics clinic. Semi-structured interviews were conducted with 40 individuals who are involved in cancer genetics research in the UK, the majority (18 clinical geneticists, 10 genetic counsellors/nurse specialists) of whom also provide a clinical service. Interviewees emphasised the need to differentiate research from clinical care for service users, and provided regulatory, ethical, economic and translational justifications for distinguishing these activities. A number of strategies for differentiating research from clinical care were described by those who work as healthcare professionals, which involved deliberately displacing these activities in time and space. It is argued that by distinguishing research from clinical care clinical researchers are engaging in a form of boundary work which enables them to manage what they experience as a conflict of interest generated by the different roles they occupy within the cancer genetics clinic. Finally, we discuss the implications of these findings for the process of informed consent.

Introduction

Research and clinical care are frequently understood as different types of activities (Wainwright, Williams, Michael, Farsides, & Cribb, 2006) – as occupying different ends of a continuum of medical work. Clinical care is seen as driven by patients’ best interests whereas research is motivated by a need to expand the evidence base or generate generalisable knowledge (Bosk, 2007, Belmont Report, 1979). Although research and care may be seen as theoretically distinct, distinguishing research from clinical care, or indeed other types of non-research activities such as clinical audit and service evaluation, may be difficult in practice (Yentis and Dawson, 2006, Bortolotti and Heinrichs, 2007). This “demarcation” problem (Gieryn, 1983) appears to be particularly prevalent within the specialty of clinical genetics (Parker, Wilkie, Ashcroft, & Kent, 2004). It has been observed that patients find it difficult to differentiate genetic testing undertaken in research protocols from that offered as part of their clinical management (Ponder et al., 2008, Cooke et al., 2008), and that researchers and healthcare professionals (Miller et al., 2008, Hallowell et al., 2009), and members of research ethics committees (Newson & Ashcroft, 2004) struggle to distinguish research from care at times.

Easter, Henderson, Davis, Churchill and King (2006) observe that researchers and research participants, while noting the differences between care and clinical research, explicitly conflate these activities and frequently describe research as a means of providing care. These authors argue that focussing upon the commonalities between research and care enables researchers to minimise the tensions which may arise from the differing duties and demands associated with simultaneously occupying the roles of scientist and healthcare professional. In contrast, it can be argued that emphasising the differences between research and non-research activities may be important for individuals who occupy potentially competing professional roles. Indeed, in his analysis of the ways in which scientists construct the relationship between science and other activities, Gieryn (1983) argues that the drawing of a (discursive or ideological) boundary between science (research) and non-science (non-research) activities – so-called “boundary work” – serves a range of social needs for researchers. He notes that distinguishing research from non-research activities serves to protect scientific autonomy by shielding researchers from political or outside interference and argues that, by ring-fencing their activities, these forms of boundary work support the pursuit of professional (i.e. personal) goals.

The ethical ramifications of failing to differentiate research and clinical care have been well documented, in particular, the implications for informed consent. A number of guidelines (e.g. Nuremberg Code, 1947, Belmont Report, 1979; Declaration of Helsinki, WMA, 2000) and oversight mechanisms (research ethics committees) have been developed to safeguard research participants’ interests, all of which stress the importance of obtaining informed consent prior to research participation. While ethical guidelines emphasise the importance of consent, there is evidence that, on occasion, consent may be “less informed” than those who are charged with the ethical oversight of research would ideally like. Research suggests that many research participants are unfamiliar with the rationale, aims and methods of scientific research. For example, studies of clinical trials have found that some participants’ understanding of concepts such as ‘equipoise’ and ‘randomisation’ is such that they see trial participation as offering them the opportunity of obtaining better or more advanced treatment (Snowdon et al., 1997, Featherstone and Donovan, 2002; Corrigan, 2003). There is increasing evidence that participants in genetic epidemiological studies see the research as offering them access to genetic testing and expect to receive personal feedback about their genetic risk status (Wendel, 2002, Gustafsson Stolt et al., 2003, Busby, 2004, Dixon-Woods et al., 2007), even when it has been explicitly stated that such information will not be forthcoming.

These findings indicate that in some instances research participants may have alternative understandings of research aims or may confound them with those of clinical practice – believing that research interventions are primarily for therapeutic benefit. Such “mis” or alternative understandings (Dixon-Woods et al., 2007) have been labelled the “therapeutic misconception” (Appelbaum and Roth, 1982, Appelbaum et al., 1987; Lidz et al., 2004; Henderson et al., 2007). The therapeutic misconception is described by Henderson et al. (2007 p. 4) as failing to understand “… that the defining purpose of clinical research is to produce generalizable knowledge”. As an understanding of both the nature (the risks and benefits of the procedures) and purpose (underlying aims and motivations) of any research intervention is regarded as necessary for informed consent, holding the therapeutic misconception is seen as potentially undermining the validity of consent.

The fact that both researchers (Joffe and Weeks, 2002, Ziebland et al., 2007) and research participants (see above) may perceive research as having a primarily therapeutic intent, suggests that holding the “therapeutic misconception” is not necessarily evidence of a lack of scientific expertise/training per se (Dixon-Woods et al., 2007), but rather reveals something about the way in which the relationship between research and clinical practice is conceived and constructed by researchers and research participants alike.

In summary, although a number of theoretical justifications are given for differentiating research from clinical care, the literature suggests that the relationship between clinical practice and research is often perceived as ambiguous and potentially contested by both research participants and clinical researchers. The research project on which this paper is based was undertaken to establish the extent to which this is the case and to explore the practical and ethical consequences. The ROCC project used qualitative methods to investigate a range of lay and professional views on the relationship between research and clinical practice in the subspecialty of cancer genetics in the UK. The data reported below were collected during interviews with individuals who carry out research in either a clinical or academic capacity. In this paper we focus upon how these researchers distinguished research from care and the reasons they gave for differentiating these activities. Our data suggest that drawing a symbolic, or actual, boundary between research and care enables researchers who also work as healthcare professionals to overcome the potentially conflicting demands and duties associated with their different professional roles. The implications of these findings for informed consent are discussed and it is argued that a reconceptualisation of informed consent may be needed.

Section snippets

Recruitment

The reasons why we chose to focus upon the subspecialty of cancer genetics in this project have been reported elsewhere (Hallowell et al., 2009). The study was approved by the Scotland A Multi-Centre Research Ethics Committee in November 2005. Potential study participants were contacted using data available within the public domain (e.g. listservs and websites) or referred to the study by colleagues who had been interviewed earlier. Purposive sampling methods were used to ensure that the sample

Results

Both researchers and healthcare professionals commented upon the vague and uncertain status of some clinic activities and the, at times, ambiguous relationship between research and clinical care (Hallowell et al., 2009); however, all were clear that cancer genetics patients should be alerted when interventions are carried out for research rather than clinical purposes. Healthcare professionals and researchers provided a number of different justifications (regulatory, ethical, economic and

Discussion

This study explored clinical and academic researchers’ perceptions of the activities which take place within the cancer genetics clinic. As we have noted elsewhere, our interviewees observed that although it is difficult to distinguish research activities from those designated as clinical care at times (Hallowell et al., 2009) it is important to emphasise the differences between these activities for patients/research participants and other key stakeholders such as regulators and funders. The

Conclusions

This paper suggests that as far as those who are involved in research in the subspecialty of cancer genetics are concerned, “care” and “research” are flexible categories which are distinguished by boundary work (Gieryn, 1983). Where this boundary falls is context dependent and varies depending upon the researcher's purpose: to satisfy governance regulations, access research funds, discharge clinical/ethical duties and develop the discipline. However, while the erection of a symbolic and/or more

Acknowledgments

Special thanks go to all the study participants, Julia Lawton for commenting on this paper, the Wessex Cancer Genetics Team in Southampton and Lesley Gardner. This research was funded by a Cancer Research UK grant [C8671/A5831] awarded to NH, MP and AL.

References (30)

  • H. Busby

    Blood donation for genetic research: what can we learn from donors’ narratives?

  • S. Cooke et al.

    Recall of participation in research projects in cancer genetics: some implications for research ethics

    Journal of Clinical Ethics

    (2008)
  • O. Corrigan

    Empty ethics: the problem with informed consent

    Sociology of Health & Illness

    (2003)
  • Cribb, A., Wainwright, S., Williams, C., Farsides, B., & Michael, M., (2007) Towards the applied: the construction of...
  • M.M. Easter et al.

    The many meanings of care in clinical research

    Sociology of Health & Illness

    (2006)
  • Cited by (45)

    • Fostering trust in healthcare: Participants’ experiences, views, and concerns about the 100,000 genomes project

      2019, European Journal of Medical Genetics
      Citation Excerpt :

      Like us, Busby found that the detail of the study was of little concern to participants; that they thought research would help future generations; and that their involvement was based on a direct “investment in[to] the future health of an imagined community, in which the NHS featured prominently” (p214). Our findings also reflect previous research showing that decision-making about whether to take part in a research study or a biorepository is not based solely on a rational choice following a weighing up of harms and benefits, but also on the complex interaction between personal, cultural, social and economic circumstances, and in the institutional context where consent is sought (Hallowell et al., 2009; Martin and Hollin, 2014; Samuel et al., 2017; Timmons and Vezyridis, 2017). Genomics England has reiterated that the 100 kG P should be “by the NHS, for the NHS”, (Martin and Hollin, 2014, p14).

    • Rhetorical and regulatory boundary-work: The case of medical cannabis policy-making in Israel

      2018, Social Science and Medicine
      Citation Excerpt :

      Indeed, boundary demarcation is now recognized as a pervasive strategy people use for diverse purposes. Several studies have shown how professionals draw boundaries to reach workable solutions in contested or conflictual areas (Brosnan et al., 2013; Duke, 2016; Ehrich et al., 2006; Hallowell et al., 2009; Wainwright et al., 2006). For example, Wainwright et al. (2006) showed how stem cell scientists presented themselves as ethical by drawing lines around which sources of embryos they agreed to work with, as well as by deferring to regulatory frameworks.

    • International clinical trials, cardiovascular disease and treatment options in the Russian Federation: Research and treatment in practice

      2015, Social Science and Medicine
      Citation Excerpt :

      Furthermore, the relations between research and treatment provision in the practice of trial conduct depend much on the kind of a trial and the conditions existing in a particular location, including the availability of adequate health care outside of research settings. For instance, the balance between research and treatment and the therapeutic beneficence of participation in cancer genetics studies in the UK (Hallowell et al., 2009) are distinct from the ones in trials of pharmacological treatments for methamphetamine dependency in the U.S. (Timmermans and McKay, 2009). Additionally, clinical trials, while themselves being facilitated by existing health disparities, have begun to fill the healthcare gap for populations with limited access to treatment (Fisher, 2009).

    • Proof of Concept of a 3 DoF Passive Exoskeleton for Reducing Low Back Musculoskeletal Disorder

      2022, 2022 IEEE 13th Annual Ubiquitous Computing, Electronics and Mobile Communication Conference, UEMCON 2022
    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text