Different beliefs about pain perception in the vegetative and minimally conscious states: a European survey of medical and paramedical professionals

https://doi.org/10.1016/S0079-6123(09)17722-1Get rights and content

Abstract

Pain management in severely brain-damaged patients constitutes a clinical and ethical stake. At the bedside, assessing the presence of pain and suffering is challenging due to both patients' physical condition and inherent limitations of clinical assessment. Neuroimaging studies support the existence of distinct cerebral responses to noxious stimulation in brain death, vegetative state, and minimally conscious state. We here provide results from a European survey on 2059 medical and paramedical professionals' beliefs on possible pain perception in patients with disorders of consciousness. To the question “Do you think that patients in a vegetative state can feel pain?,” 68% of the interviewed paramedical caregivers (n=538) and 56% of medical doctors (n=1166) answered “yes” (no data on exact profession in 17% of total sample). Logistic regression analysis showed that paramedical professionals, religious caregivers, and older caregivers reported more often that vegetative patients may experience pain. Following professional background, religion was the highest predictor of caregivers' opinion: 64% of religious (n=1009; 850 Christians) versus 52% of nonreligious respondents (n=830) answered positively (missing data on religion in 11% of total sample). To the question “Do you think that patients in a minimally conscious state can feel pain?” nearly all interviewed caregivers answered “yes” (96% of the medical doctors and 97% of the paramedical caregivers). Women and religious caregivers reported more often that minimally conscious patients may experience pain. These results are discussed in terms of existing definitions of pain and suffering, the remaining uncertainty on the clinical assessment of pain as a subjective first-person experience and recent functional neuroimaging findings on nociceptive processing in disorders of consciousness. In our view, more research is needed to increase our understanding of residual sensation in vegetative and minimally conscious patients and to propose evidence-based medical guidelines for the management of possible pain perception and suffering in these vulnerable patient populations.

Introduction

The International Association for the Study of Pain (IASP, 1994) defines pain as “an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with real or potential tissue damage.” As stressed by the IASP, the inability to communicate verbally does not negate the possibility that an individual is experiencing pain and is in need of appropriate pain-relieving treatment. Pain may also be reported in the absence of tissue damage or any likely pathophysiological cause; usually this happens for psychological reasons. Activity induced in the nociceptor and nociceptive pathways by a noxious stimulus is not pain, which is always a psychological state, even though pain most often has a proximate physical cause. Pain is a subjective first-person experience with both physical and affective aspects (Kupers et al., 2005). It is a sensation in a part or parts of the body, which is, always unpleasant and, therefore, an emotional experience. Pain and suffering are not interchangeable constructs. However, the concept of suffering is surprisingly ill defined and given relatively little attention in medicine. A person might experience significant pain-related suffering from a relatively low-level noxious stimulation if she or he believes the implications are ominous, interminable, and beyond their control (Turk and Wilson, 2009). Cassell (1991) defined suffering as “the state of severe distress associated with events that threaten the intactness of the person.” Pain by itself does not seem to be sufficient to cause suffering; rather it seems that the person's interpretation of the symptoms is crucial. We will here consider (as expressed by the Multi-Society Task Force on PVS, 1994) that pain and suffering refer to the unpleasant experiences that occur in response to stimulation of peripheral nociceptive receptors and their peripheral and central afferent pathways or that they may emanate endogenously from the depths of human self-perception.

The management of pain and suffering in disorders of consciousness (DOCs) is challenging because, by definition, patients in a vegetative state (VS) or minimally conscious state (MCS) cannot verbally or nonverbally communicate their feelings or experiences (e.g., McQuillen, 1991; Bernat, 2006; Laureys and Boly, 2007). The VS is a condition of preserved wakefulness contrasted with absent voluntary interaction with the environment (Jennett and Plum, 1972). The MCS was only recently defined (Giacino et al., 2002) and is characterized by discernible but fluctuating signs of awareness without consistent communication with the environment. How can we know if patients in VS or in MCS feel pain or suffering? The perceptions of pain and suffering are conscious experiences: the wakeful unconsciousness of vegetative patients, by definition, precludes these experiences. Of course, there is a theoretical problem to evaluate the subjective experience of pain (and any other conscious perception or thought) in another person. At the patient's bedside, we are limited to evaluate the behavioral responsiveness to pain. If patients never show any sign of voluntary movement in response to noxious stimuli it will be concluded they do not experience pain. They may, however, be aroused by noxious stimuli by opening their eyes if they are closed, quickening their breathing, increasing heart rate and blood pressure, and occasionally show grimace-like or crying-like behavior. As all these abilities are also seen in infants with anencephaly (The Medical Task Force on Anencephaly, 1990; Payne and Taylor, 1997) they are considered to be of subcortical origin and not necessarily reflecting conscious perception of pain. We also know from studies in general anesthesia that motor or autonomic responses are no reliable indicators of consciousness (e.g., Halliburton, 1998).

DOC patients classically are bed- or chair-bound and may suffer from spasticity, contractures, fractures, pressure sores, soft tissue ischemia, peripheral nerve injuries, complex regional pain syndrome, central pain syndromes, and post-surgical incisional pain (Schnakers and Zasler, 2007). Since they cannot communicate their potential painful state, the existence of pain is clinically inferred from observing their spontaneous behavior or their motor responses to noxious stimulation. Stereotyped responses (i.e., slow generalized flexion or extension of the upper and lower extremities), flexion withdrawal (i.e., withdrawal of the limb away from the point of the stimulation), and localization responses (i.e., the nonstimulated limb locates and makes contact with the stimulated body part at the point of stimulation) are linked to, respectively, brainstem, subcortical, or cortical activity (e.g., Stevens and Nyquist, 2006). No response after intense noxious stimulation reveals a deep stage of coma; stereotyped responses are considered as “automatic” unconscious reflexes, whereas localization of noxious stimulation is usually considered as indicative of conscious perception (Posner et al., 2007).

Repeated clinical examinations by trained and experienced examiners are paramount for the behavioral assessment of pain. To date, several scales are used for assessing pain in noncommunicative individuals with end-stage dementia, in newborns and in sedated intensive care patients, but no scale was developed to assess pain in DOCs (Schnakers et al., 2009b). We therefore recently proposed the Nociception Coma Scale as a standardized and validated tool measuring motor, verbal, and visual responses and facial expression in response to pain (Schnakers et al., 2009a). However, the absence of a behavioral response cannot be taken as an absolute proof of the absence of consciousness (McQuillen, 1991; Bernat, 1992) and inferring pain and suffering solely by observing behavioral responses may be misleading, especially in patients with extreme motor impairment or with fluctuating levels of vigilance (e.g., Majerus et al., 2005). Given these limitations of our bedside clinical assessment of pain in noncommunicative brain injured patients, inherent to the first-person subjective dimension of pain, we will next review the usefulness of functional neuroimaging methods in the study of pain and suffering in VS and MCS.

Section snippets

Neuroimaging of pain

Since brain responses are the final common pathway in behavioral responses to pain (unconscious and conscious), we believe that the application of functional imaging will allow us to study pain in an objective manner and to propose evidence-based guidelines on the use of analgesia and symptom management in DOCs (e.g., Borsook and Becerra, 2006; Laureys et al., 2006; Laureys and Boly, 2008). In healthy controls, studies with positron emission tomography (PET) and functional magnetic resonance

Attitudes toward pain perception

To our knowledge, no data exist on the thoughts of physicians and paramedical personnel toward pain perception in patients in VS as compared to MCS. We here present results from a questionnaire survey on attitudes on DOCs, which was distributed during lectures at medical and scientific conferences and meetings (n=48) within Europe (data were collected by SL, AD, MAB, AV, MAB, and DL between June 2007 and April 2009). Participation to the survey was voluntary and anonymous. Participants were

Acknowledgments

This work was supported by the Belgian Ministry of Health (SPF Santé Publique), Belgian Fonds de la Recherche Scientifique (FRS), European Commission (DISCOS, Mindbridge, COST), Belgian French Community Concerted Research Action, McDonnell Foundation, Mind Science Foundation, Reine Elisabeth Medical Foundation, and University and University Hospital of Liège. S. Laureys is Senior Research Associate, C. Schnakers and M. Boly are Postdoctoral Researchers, C. Chatelle and M. A. Bruno are Research

References (61)

  • S. Laureys et al.

    Brain function in coma, vegetative state, and related disorders

    Lancet Neurology

    (2004)
  • S. Majerus et al.

    Behavioral evaluation of consciousness in severe brain damage

    Progress in Brain Research

    (2005)
  • R. Peyron et al.

    Functional imaging of brain responses to pain. A review and meta- analysis

    Neurophysiologie Clinique

    (2000)
  • R.A. Poldrack

    The role of fMRI in cognitive neuroscience: Where do we stand?

    Current Opinion in Neurobiology

    (2008)
  • C. Schnakers et al.

    Ethical Implications: Pain, coma, and related disorders

  • R.D. Stevens et al.

    Coma, delirium, and cognitive dysfunction in critical illness

    Critical Care Clinics

    (2006)
  • A. Vanhaudenhuyse et al.

    Pain and non-pain processing during hypnosis: A thulium-YAG event related fMRI study

    Neuroimage

    (2009)
  • K.J. Anand et al.

    New perspectives on the definition of pain

    Pain

    (1996)
  • K.J. Anand et al.

    Pain and its effects in the human neonate and fetus

    The New England Journal of Medicine

    (1987)
  • K. Andrews et al.

    Misdiagnosis of the vegetative state: Retrospective study in a rehabilitation unit

    British Medical Journal

    (1996)
  • J.L. Bernat

    The boundaries of the persistent vegetative state

    Journal of Clinical Ethics

    (1992)
  • M. Boly et al.

    Baseline brain activity fluctuations predict somatosensory perception in humans

    Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America

    (2007)
  • M. Boly et al.

    Cerebral processing of auditory and noxious stimuli in severely brain injured patients: Differences between VS and MCS

    Neuropsychological Rehabilitation

    (2005)
  • D. Borsook et al.

    Breaking down the barriers: fMRI applications in pain, analgesia and analgesics

    Molecular Pain [electronic resource]

    (2006)
  • P. Boveroux et al.

    Brain function in physiologically, pharmacologically and pathologically altered states of consciousness

    International Anesthesiology Clinics

    (2008)
  • E.J. Cassell

    Recognizing suffering

    The Hastings Center Report

    (1991)
  • N.L. Childs et al.

    Accuracy of diagnosis of persistent vegetative state

    Neurology

    (1993)
  • N.A. Christakis et al.

    Physician characteristics associated with decisions to withdraw life support

    American Journal of Public Health

    (1995)
  • Daroff, R. B. (1990). The American Neurological Association survey results on PVS. Paper presented at 115th Annual...
  • A. Demertzi et al.

    Dualism persists in the science of mind

    Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

    (2009)
  • Cited by (77)

    • Diagnosis, prognosis and treatment in disorders of consciousness

      2018, NPG Neurologie - Psychiatrie - Geriatrie
    • Assessing pain in patients with chronic disorders of consciousness: Are we heading in the right direction?

      2017, Consciousness and Cognition
      Citation Excerpt :

      Patients in a Minimally Conscious State (MCS) (Giacino et al., 2002) or exhibiting Unresponsive Wakefulness Syndrome (UWS) (previously referred to as Vegetative State), both belong to the chronic Disorders of Consciousness (DoC), and show inconsistent and only reflex responses, respectively, to all types of stimuli. However, the absence of a purposeful motor response to stimuli does not necessarily mean that a patient with a DoC lacks awareness (de Tommaso et al., 2013, 2015; Demertzi et al., 2009). In fact, advanced paraclinical approaches have revealed concealed command-following behaviors and residual higher-level cognitive capacities in patients who are otherwise defined as being in the UWS state (Bardin et al., 2011; Forgacs et al., 2014; Goldfine, Victor, Conte, Bardin, & Schiff, 2011; Monti et al., 2010; Owen et al., 2006; Stender et al., 2014).

    • Do unresponsive wakefulness syndrome patients feel pain? Role of laser-evoked potential-induced gamma-band oscillations in detecting cortical pain processing

      2016, Neuroscience
      Citation Excerpt :

      Nonetheless, lack of purposeful pain-related behaviors do not demonstrate that all the UWS patients are incapable of consciously feeling pain, since some among them may have a covert awareness, i.e. they could be aware but unable to behaviorally manifest it. In other words, they cannot show more than reflex behaviors, although aware of perceiving external stimuli (Formisano et al., 2011a,b, 2013; Demertzi et al., 2009; Bruno et al., 2011). Indeed, such individuals suffer from functional locked-in syndrome (fLIS), being thus unable to show purposeful motor behavior owing to a severe motor output impairment rather than a thalamo-cortical functional disconnectivity.

    View all citing articles on Scopus

    Both A. Demertzi and C. Schnakers have contributed equally to this study.

    View full text